NOTICE:鈥俆his opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the United States Reports.鈥僐eaders are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 12鈥1168
_________________
ELEANOR McCULLEN, et al., PETITIONERS v. MARTHA COAKLEY, ATTORNEY GEN-ERAL of MASSACHUSETTS, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the first circuit
[June 26, 2014]
Chief Justice Roberts delivered the opinion of the Court.
A Massachusetts statute makes it a crime to knowingly stand on a 鈥減ublic way or sidewalk鈥 within 35 feet of an entrance or driveway to any place, other than a hospital, where abortions are performed. Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, 搂搂120E陆(a), (b) (West 2012). Petitioners are individuals who approach and talk to women outside such facilities, attempting to dissuade them from having abortions. The statute prevents petitioners from doing so near the facilities鈥 entrances. The question presented is whether the statute violates the First Amendment.
I
A
In 2000, the Massachusetts Legislature enacted the Massachusetts Reproductive Health Care Facilities Act, Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, 搂120E陆 (West 2000). The law was designed to address clashes between abortion opponents and advocates of abortion rights that were occurring outside clinics where abortions were performed. The Act established a defined area with an 18-foot radius around the entrances and driveways of such facilities. 搂120E陆(b). Anyone could enter that area, but once within it, no one (other than certain exempt individuals) could knowingly approach within six feet of another person鈥攗nless that person consented鈥斺渇or the purpose of passing a leaflet or handbill to, displaying a sign to, or engaging in oral protest, education, or counseling with such other person.鈥 Ibid. A separate provision subjected to criminal punishment anyone who 鈥渒nowingly obstructs, detains, hinders, impedes or blocks another person鈥檚 entry to or exit from a reproductive health care facility.鈥 搂120E陆(e).
The statute was modeled on a similar Colorado law that this Court had upheld in Hill v. Colorado, 530 U. S. 703 (2000) . Relying on Hill, the United States Court of Appeals for the First Circuit sustained the Massachusetts statute against a First Amendment challenge. McGuire v. Reilly, 386 F. 3d 45 (2004) (McGuire II), cert. denied, 544 U. S. 974 (2005) ; McGuire v. Reilly, 260 F. 3d 36 (2001) (McGuire I).
By 2007, some Massachusetts legislators and law enforcement officials had come to regard the 2000 statute as inadequate. At legislative hearings, multiple witnesses recounted apparent violations of the law. Massachusetts Attorney General Martha Coakley, for example, testified that protestors violated the statute 鈥渙n a routine basis.鈥 App. 78. To illustrate this claim, she played a video depicting protestors approaching patients and clinic staff within the buffer zones, ostensibly without the latter individuals鈥 consent. Clinic employees and volunteers also testified that protestors congregated near the doors and in the driveways of the clinics, with the result that prospective patients occasionally retreated from the clinics rather than try to make their way to the clinic entrances or parking lots.
Captain William B. Evans of the Boston Police Department, however, testified that his officers had made 鈥渘o more than five or so arrests鈥 at the Planned Parenthood clinic in Boston and that what few prosecutions had been brought were unsuccessful. Id., at 68鈥69. Witnesses attributed the dearth of enforcement to the difficulty of policing the six-foot no-approach zones. Captain Evans testified that the 18-foot zones were so crowded with protestors that they resembled 鈥渁 goalie鈥檚 crease,鈥 making it hard to determine whether a protestor had deliberately approached a patient or, if so, whether the patient had consented. Id., at 69鈥71. For similar reasons, Attorney General Coakley concluded that the six-foot no-approach zones were 鈥渦nenforceable.鈥 Id., at 79. What the police needed, she said, was a fixed buffer zone around clinics that protestors could not enter. Id., at 74, 76. Captain Evans agreed, explaining that such a zone would 鈥渕ake our job so much easier.鈥 Id., at 68.
To address these concerns, the Massachusetts Legislature amended the statute in 2007, replacing the six-foot no-approach zones (within the 18-foot area) with a 35-foot fixed buffer zone from which individuals are categorically excluded. The statute now provides:
鈥淣o person shall knowingly enter or remain on a public way or sidewalk adjacent to a reproductive health care facility within a radius of 35 feet of any portion of an entrance, exit or driveway of a reproductive health care facility or within the area within a rectangle created by extending the outside boundaries of any entrance, exit or driveway of a reproductive health care facility in straight lines to the point where such lines intersect the sideline of the street in front of such entrance, exit or driveway.鈥 Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, 搂120E陆(b) (West 2012).
A 鈥渞eproductive health care facility,鈥 in turn, is defined as 鈥渁 place, other than within or upon the grounds of a hospital, where abortions are offered or performed.鈥 搂120E陆(a).
The 35-foot buffer zone applies only 鈥渄uring a facility鈥檚 business hours,鈥 and the area must be 鈥渃learly marked and posted.鈥 搂120E陆(c). In practice, facilities typically mark the zones with painted arcs and posted signs on adjacent sidewalks and streets. A first violation of the statute is punishable by a fine of up to $500, up to three months in prison, or both, while a subsequent offense is punishable by a fine of between $500 and $5,000, up to two and a half years in prison, or both. 搂120E陆(d).
The Act exempts four classes of individuals: (1) 鈥減ersons entering or leaving such facility鈥; (2) 鈥渆mployees or agents of such facility acting within the scope of their employment鈥; (3) 鈥渓aw enforcement, ambulance, firefighting, construction, utilities, public works and other municipal agents acting within the scope of their employment鈥; and (4) 鈥減ersons using the public sidewalk or street right-of-way adjacent to such facility solely for the purposeof reaching a destination other than such facility.鈥 搂120E陆(b)(1)鈥(4). The legislature also retained the separate provision from the 2000 version that proscribes the knowing obstruction of access to a facility. 搂120E陆(e).
B
Some of the individuals who stand outside Massachusetts abortion clinics are fairly described as protestors, who express their moral or religious opposition to abortion through signs and chants or, in some cases, more aggressive methods such as face-to-face confrontation. Petitioners take a different tack. They attempt to engage women approaching the clinics in what they call 鈥渟idewalk counseling,鈥 which involves offering information about alternatives to abortion and help pursuing those options. Petitioner Eleanor McCullen, for instance, will typically initiate a conversation this way: 鈥淕ood morning, may I give you my literature? Is there anything I can do for you? I鈥檓 available if you have any questions.鈥 App. 138. If the woman seems receptive, McCullen will provide additional information. McCullen and the other petitioners consider it essential to maintain a caring demeanor, a calm tone of voice, and direct eye contact during these exchanges. Such interactions, petitioners believe, are a much more effective means of dissuading women from having abortions than confrontational methods such as shouting or brandishing signs, which in petitioners鈥 view tend only to antagonize their intended audience. In unrefuted testimony, petitioners say they have collectively persuaded hundreds of women to forgo abortions.
The buffer zones have displaced petitioners from their previous positions outside the clinics. McCullen offers counseling outside a Planned Parenthood clinic in Boston, as do petitioners Jean Zarrella and Eric Cadin. Petitioner Gregory Smith prays the rosary there. The clinic occupies its own building on a street corner. Its main door is recessed into an open foyer, approximately 12 feet back from the public sidewalk. Before the Act was amended to create the buffer zones, petitioners stood near the entryway to the foyer. Now a buffer zone鈥攎arked by a painted arc and a sign鈥攕urrounds the entrance. This zone extends 23 feet down the sidewalk in one direction, 26 feet in the other, and outward just one foot short of the curb. The clinic鈥檚 entrance adds another seven feet to the width of the zone. Id., at 293鈥295. The upshot is that petitioners are effectively excluded from a 56-foot-wide expanse of the public sidewalk in front of the clinic.[1]
Petitioners Mark Bashour and Nancy Clark offer counseling and information outside a Planned Parenthood clinic in Worcester. Unlike the Boston clinic, the Worcester clinic sits well back from the public street and sidewalks. Patients enter the clinic in one of two ways. Those arriving on foot turn off the public sidewalk and walk down a nearly 54-foot-long private walkway to the main entrance. More than 85% of patients, however, arrive by car, turning onto the clinic鈥檚 driveway from the street, parking in a private lot, and walking to the main entrance on a private walkway.
Bashour and Clark would like to stand where the private walkway or driveway intersects the sidewalk and offer leaflets to patients as they walk or drive by. But a painted arc extends from the private walkway 35 feet down the sidewalk in either direction and outward nearly to the curb on the opposite side of the street. Another arc surrounds the driveway鈥檚 entrance, covering more than 93 feet of the sidewalk (including the width of the driveway) and extending across the street and nearly six feet onto the sidewalk on the opposite side. Id., at 295鈥297. Bashour and Clark must now stand either some distance down the sidewalk from the private walkway and driveway or across the street.
Petitioner Cyril Shea stands outside a Planned Parenthood clinic in Springfield, which, like the Worcester clinic, is set back from the public streets. Approximately 90% of patients arrive by car and park in the private lots surrounding the clinic. Shea used to position himself at an entrance to one of the five driveways leading to the parking lots. Painted arcs now surround the entrances, each spanning approximately 100 feet of the sidewalk parallel to the street (again, including the width of the driveways) and extending outward well into the street. Id., at 297鈥299. Like petitioners at the Worcester clinic, Shea now stands far down the sidewalk from the driveway entrances.
Petitioners at all three clinics claim that the buffer zones have considerably hampered their counseling efforts. Although they have managed to conduct some counseling and to distribute some literature outside the buffer zones鈥攑articularly at the Boston clinic鈥攖hey say they have had many fewer conversations and distributed many fewer leaflets since the zones went into effect. Id., at 136鈥137, 180, 200.
The second statutory exemption allows clinic employees and agents acting within the scope of their employment to enter the buffer zones. Relying on this exemption, the Boston clinic uses 鈥渆scorts鈥 to greet women as they approach the clinic, accompanying them through the zones to the clinic entrance. Petitioners claim that the escorts sometimes thwart petitioners鈥 attempts to communicate with patients by blocking petitioners from handing literature to patients, telling patients not to 鈥減ay any attention鈥 or 鈥渓isten to鈥 petitioners, and disparaging petitioners as 鈥渃razy.鈥 Id., at 165, 178.
C
In January 2008, petitioners sued Attorney General Coakley and other Commonwealth officials. They sought to enjoin enforcement of the Act, alleging that it violates the First and Fourteenth Amendments, both on its face and as applied to them. The District Court denied petitioners鈥 facial challenge after a bench trial based on a stipulated record. 573 F. Supp. 2d 382 (Mass. 2008).
The Court of Appeals for the First Circuit affirmed. 571 F. 3d 167 (2009). Relying extensively on its previous decisions upholding the 2000 version of the Act, see McGuire II, 386 F. 3d 45; McGuire I, 260 F. 3d 36, the court upheld the 2007 version as a reasonable 鈥渢ime, place, and manner鈥 regulation under the test set forth in Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 (1989) . 571 F. 3d, at 174鈥181. It also rejected petitioners鈥 arguments that the Act was substantially overbroad, void for vagueness, and an impermissible prior restraint. Id., at 181鈥184.
The case then returned to the District Court, which held that the First Circuit鈥檚 decision foreclosed all but one of petitioners鈥 as-applied challenges. 759 F. Supp. 2d 133 (2010). After another bench trial, it denied the remain-ing as-applied challenge, finding that the Act left petitioners ample alternative channels of communication. 844 F. Supp. 2d 206 (2012). The Court of Appeals once again affirmed. 708 F. 3d 1 (2013).
We granted certiorari. 570 U. S. ___ (2013).
II
By its very terms, the Massachusetts Act regulates access to 鈥減ublic way[s]鈥 and 鈥渟idewalk[s].鈥 Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, 搂120E陆(b) (Supp. 2007). Such areas occupy a 鈥渟pecial position in terms of First Amendment protection鈥 because of their historic role as sites for discussion and debate. United States v. Grace, 461 U. S. 171, 180 (1983) . These places鈥攚hich we have labeled 鈥渢raditional public fora鈥濃斺 鈥榟ave immemorially been held in trust for the use of the public and, time out of mind, have been used for purposes of assembly, communicating thoughts between citizens, and discussing public questions.鈥 鈥 Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, 555 U. S. 460, 469 (2009) (quoting Perry Ed. Assn. v. Perry Local Educators鈥 Assn., 460 U. S. 37, 45 (1983) ).
It is no accident that public streets and sidewalks have developed as venues for the exchange of ideas. Even today, they remain one of the few places where a speaker can be confident that he is not simply preaching to the choir. With respect to other means of communication, an individual confronted with an uncomfortable message can always turn the page, change the channel, or leave the Web site. Not so on public streets and sidewalks. There, a listener often encounters speech he might otherwise tune out. In light of the First Amendment鈥檚 purpose 鈥渢o preserve an uninhibited marketplace of ideas in which truth will ultimately prevail,鈥 FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U. S. 364, 377 (1984) (internal quotation marks omitted), this aspect of traditional public fora is a virtue, not a vice.
In short, traditional public fora are areas that have historically been open to the public for speech activities. Thus, even though the Act says nothing about speech on its face, there is no doubt鈥攁nd respondents do not dispute鈥攖hat it restricts access to traditional public fora and is therefore subject to First Amendment scrutiny. See Brief for Respondents 26 (although 鈥淸b]y its terms, the Act regulates only conduct,鈥 it 鈥渋ncidentally regulates the place and time of protected speech鈥).
Consistent with the traditionally open character of public streets and sidewalks, we have held that the government鈥檚 ability to restrict speech in such locations is 鈥渧ery limited.鈥 Grace, supra, at 177. In particular, the guiding First Amendment principle that the 鈥済overnment has no power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content鈥 applies with full force in a traditional public forum. Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92, 95 (1972) . As a general rule, in such a forum the government may not 鈥渟electively . . . shield the public from some kinds of speech on the ground that they are more offensive than others.鈥 Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S. 205, 209 (1975) .
We have, however, afforded the government somewhat wider leeway to regulate features of speech unrelated to its content. 鈥淸E]ven in a public forum the government may impose reasonable restrictions on the time, place, or manner of protected speech, provided the restrictions 鈥榓re justified without reference to the content of the regulated speech, that they are narrowly tailored to serve a significant governmental interest, and that they leave open ample alternative channels for communication of the information.鈥 鈥 Ward, 491 U. S., at 791 (quoting Clark v. Community for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U. S. 288, 293 (1984) ).[2]
While the parties agree that this test supplies theproper framework for assessing the constitutionality of the Massachusetts Act, they disagree about whether the Act satisfies the test鈥檚 three requirements.
III
Petitioners contend that the Act is not content neutral for two independent reasons: First, they argue that it discriminates against abortion-related speech because it establishes buffer zones only at clinics that perform abortions. Second, petitioners contend that the Act, by exempting clinic employees and agents, favors one viewpoint about abortion over the other. If either of these arguments is correct, then the Act must satisfy strict scrutiny鈥攖hat is, it must be the least restrictive means of achieving a compelling state interest. See United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc., 529 U. S. 803, 813 (2000) . Respondents do not argue that the Act can survive this exacting standard.
Justice Scalia objects to our decision to consider whether the statute is content based and thus subject to strict scrutiny, given that we ultimately conclude that it is not narrowly tailored. Post, at 2 (opinion concurring in judgment). But we think it unexceptional to perform the first part of a multipart constitutional analysis first. The content-neutrality prong of the Ward test is logically antecedent to the narrow-tailoring prong, because it determines the appropriate level of scrutiny. It is not unusual for the Court to proceed sequentially in applying a constitutional test, even when the preliminary steps turn out not to be dispositive. See, e.g., Bartnicki v. Vopper, 532 U. S. 514 鈥527 (2001); Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project, 561 U. S. 1 鈥28 (2010) (concluding that a law was content based even though it ultimately survived strict scrutiny).
The Court does sometimes assume, without deciding, that a law is subject to a less stringent level of scrutiny, as we did earlier this Term in McCutcheon v. Federal Election Commission, 572 U. S. ___, ___ (2014) (plurality opinion) (slip op., at 10). But the distinction between that case and this one seems clear: Applying any standard of review other than intermediate scrutiny in McCutcheon鈥攖he standard that was assumed to apply鈥攚ould have required overruling a precedent. There is no similar reason to forgo the ordinary order of operations in this case.
At the same time, there is good reason to address content neutrality. In discussing whether the Act is narrowly tailored, see Part IV, infra, we identify a number of less-restrictive alternative measures that the Massachusetts Legislature might have adopted. Some apply only at abortion clinics, which raises the question whether those provisions are content neutral. See infra, at 12鈥15. While we need not (and do not) endorse any of those measures, it would be odd to consider them as possible alternatives if they were presumptively unconstitutional because they were content based and thus subject to strict scrutiny.
A
The Act applies only at a 鈥渞eproductive health care facility,鈥 defined as 鈥渁 place, other than within or upon the grounds of a hospital, where abortions are offered or performed.鈥 Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, 搂120E陆(a). Given this definition, petitioners argue, 鈥渧irtually all speech affected by the Act is speech concerning abortion,鈥 thus rendering the Act content based. Brief for Petitioners 23.
We disagree. To begin, the Act does not draw content-based distinctions on its face. Contrast Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312, 315 (1988) (ordinance prohibiting the display within 500 feet of a foreign embassy of any sign that tends to bring the foreign government into 鈥 鈥榩ublic odium鈥 鈥 or 鈥 鈥榩ublic disrepute鈥 鈥); Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S. 455, 465 (1980) (statute prohibiting all residential picketing except 鈥減eaceful labor picketing鈥). The Act would be content based if it required 鈥渆nforcement authorities鈥 to 鈥渆xamine the content of the message that is conveyed to determine whether鈥 a violation has occurred. League of Women Voters of Cal., supra, at 383. But it does not. Whether petitioners violate the Act 鈥渄epends鈥 not 鈥渙n what they say,鈥 Humanitarian Law Project, supra, at 27, but simply on where they say it. Indeed, petitioners can violate the Act merely by standing in a buffer zone, without displaying a sign or uttering a word.
It is true, of course, that by limiting the buffer zones to abortion clinics, the Act has the 鈥渋nevitable effect鈥 of restricting abortion-related speech more than speech on other subjects. Brief for Petitioners 24 (quoting United States v. O鈥橞rien, 391 U. S. 367, 384 (1968) ). But a facially neutral law does not become content based simply be-cause it may disproportionately affect speech on certain topics. On the contrary, 鈥淸a] regulation that serves purposes unrelated to the content of expression is deemed neutral, even if it has an incidental effect on some speakers or messages but not others.鈥 Ward, supra, at 791. The question in such a case is whether the law is 鈥 鈥榡ustified without reference to the content of the regulated speech.鈥 鈥 Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41, 48 (1986) (quoting Virginia Pharmacy Board v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U. S. 748, 771 (1976) ; emphasis deleted).
The Massachusetts Act is. Its stated purpose is to 鈥渋ncrease forthwith public safety at reproductive health care facilities.鈥 2007 Mass. Acts p. 660. Respondents have articulated similar purposes before this Court鈥攏amely, 鈥減ublic safety, patient access to healthcare, and the unobstructed use of public sidewalks and roadways.鈥 Brief for Respondents 27; see, e.g., App. 51 (testimony of Attorney General Coakley); id., at 67鈥70 (testimony of Captain William B. Evans of the Boston Police); id., at 79鈥80 (testimony of Mary Beth Heffernan, Undersecretary for Criminal Justice); id., at 122鈥124 (affidavit of Captain Evans). It is not the case that 鈥淸e]very objective indication shows that the provision鈥檚 primary purpose is to restrict speech that opposes abortion.鈥 Post, at 7.
We have previously deemed the foregoing concerns to be content neutral. See Boos, 485 U. S., at 321 (identifying 鈥渃ongestion,鈥 鈥渋nterference with ingress or egress,鈥 and 鈥渢he need to protect . . . security鈥 as content-neutral concerns). Obstructed access and congested sidewalks are problems no matter what caused them. A group of individuals can obstruct clinic access and clog sidewalks just as much when they loiter as when they protest abortion or counsel patients.
To be clear, the Act would not be content neutral if it were concerned with undesirable effects that arise from 鈥渢he direct impact of speech on its audience鈥 or 鈥淸l]isteners鈥 reactions to speech.鈥 Ibid. If, for example, the speech outside Massachusetts abortion clinics caused offense or made listeners uncomfortable, such offense or discomfort would not give the Commonwealth a content-neutral justification to restrict the speech. All of the problems identified by the Commonwealth here, however, arise irrespective of any listener鈥檚 reactions. Whether or not a single person reacts to abortion protestors鈥 chants or petitioners鈥 counseling, large crowds outside abortion clinics can still compromise public safety, impede access, and obstruct sidewalks.
Petitioners do not really dispute that the Commonwealth鈥檚 interests in ensuring safety and preventing obstruction are, as a general matter, content neutral. But petitioners note that these interests 鈥渁pply outside every building in the State that hosts any activity that might occasion protest or comment,鈥 not just abortion clinics. Brief for Petitioners 24. By choosing to pursue these interests only at abortion clinics, petitioners argue, the Massachusetts Legislature evinced a purpose to 鈥渟ingle[ ] out for regulation speech about one particular topic: abortion.鈥 Reply Brief 9.
We cannot infer such a purpose from the Act鈥檚 limited scope. The broad reach of a statute can help confirm that it was not enacted to burden a narrower category of disfavored speech. See Kagan, Private Speech, Public Purpose: The Role of Governmental Motive in First Amendment Doctrine, 63 U. Chi. L. Rev. 413, 451鈥452 (1996). At the same time, however, 鈥淪tates adopt laws to address the problems that confront them. The First Amendment does not require States to regulate for problems that do not exist.鈥 Burson v. Freeman, 504 U. S. 191, 207 (1992) (plurality opinion). The Massachusetts Legislature amended the Act in 2007 in response to a problem that was, in its experience, limited to abortion clinics. There was a record of crowding, obstruction, and even violence outside such clinics. There were apparently no similar recurring problems associated with other kinds of healthcare facilities, let alone with 鈥渆very building in the State that hosts any activity that might occasion protest or comment.鈥 Brief for Petitioners 24. In light of the limited nature of the problem, it was reasonable for the Massachusetts Legislature to enact a limited solution. When selecting among various options for combating a particular problem, legislatures should be encouraged to choose the one that restricts less speech, not more.
Justice Scalia objects that the statute does restrict more speech than necessary, because 鈥渙nly one [Massachusetts abortion clinic] is known to have been beset by the problems that the statute supposedly addresses.鈥 Post, at 7. But there are no grounds for inferring content-based discrimination here simply because the legislature acted with respect to abortion facilities generally rather than proceeding on a facility-by-facility basis. On these facts, the poor fit noted by Justice Scalia goes to the question of narrow tailoring, which we consider below. See infra, at 26鈥28.
B
Petitioners also argue that the Act is content based because it exempts four classes of individuals, Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, 搂搂120E陆(b)(1)鈥(4), one of which comprises 鈥渆mployees or agents of [a reproductive healthcare] facil-ity acting within the scope of their employment.鈥 搂120E陆(b)(2). This exemption, petitioners say, favors one side in the abortion debate and thus constitutes viewpoint discrimination鈥攁n 鈥渆gregious form of content discrimination,鈥 Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S. 819, 829 (1995) . In particular, petitioners argue that the exemption allows clinic employees and agents鈥攊ncluding the volunteers who 鈥渆scort鈥 patients arriving at the Boston clinic鈥攖o speak inside the buffer zones.
It is of course true that 鈥渁n exemption from an otherwise permissible regulation of speech may represent a governmental 鈥榓ttempt to give one side of a debatable public question an advantage in expressing its views to the people.鈥 鈥 City of Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U. S. 43, 51 (1994) (quoting First Nat. Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 鈥786 (1978)). At least on the record before us, however, the statutory exemption for clinic employees and agents acting within the scope of their employment does not appear to be such an attempt.
There is nothing inherently suspect about providing some kind of exemption to allow individuals who work at the clinics to enter or remain within the buffer zones. In particular, the exemption cannot be regarded as simply a carve-out for the clinic escorts; it also covers employees such as the maintenance worker shoveling a snowy sidewalk or the security guard patrolling a clinic entrance, see App. 95 (affidavit of Michael T. Baniukiewicz).
Given the need for an exemption for clinic employees, the 鈥渟cope of their employment鈥 qualification simply ensures that the exemption is limited to its purpose of allowing the employees to do their jobs. It performs the same function as the identical 鈥渟cope of their employment鈥 restriction on the exemption for 鈥渓aw enforcement, ambulance, fire-fighting, construction, utilities, public works and other municipal agents.鈥 搂120E陆(b)(3). Contrary to the suggestion of Justice Scalia, post, at 11鈥12, there is little reason to suppose that the Massachusetts Legislature intended to incorporate a common law doctrine developed for determining vicarious liability in tort when it used the phrase 鈥渟cope of their employment鈥 for the wholly different purpose of defining the scope of an exemption to a criminal statute. The limitation instead makes clear鈥攚ith respect to both clinic employees and municipal agents鈥攖hat exempted individuals are allowed inside the zones only to perform those acts authorized by their employers. There is no suggestion in the record that any of the clinics authorize their employees to speak about abortion in the buffer zones. The 鈥渟cope of their employment鈥 limitation thus seems designed to protect against exactly the sort of conduct that petitioners and Justice Scalia fear.
Petitioners did testify in this litigation about instances in which escorts at the Boston clinic had expressed views about abortion to the women they were accompanying, thwarted petitioners鈥 attempts to speak and hand literature to the women, and disparaged petitioners in various ways. See App. 165, 168鈥169, 177鈥178, 189鈥190. It is unclear from petitioners鈥 testimony whether these alleged incidents occurred within the buffer zones. There is no viewpoint discrimination problem if the incidents occurred outside the zones because petitioners are equally free to say whatever they would like in that area.
Even assuming the incidents occurred inside the zones, the record does not suggest that they involved speech within the scope of the escorts鈥 employment. If the speech was beyond the scope of their employment, then each of the alleged incidents would violate the Act鈥檚 express terms. Petitioners鈥 complaint would then be that the police were failing to enforce the Act equally against clinic escorts. Cf. Hoye v. City of Oakland, 653 F. 3d 835, 849鈥852 (CA9 2011) (finding selective enforcement of a similar ordinance in Oakland, California). While such allegations might state a claim of official viewpoint discrimination, that would not go to the validity of the Act. In any event, petitioners nowhere allege selective enforcement.
It would be a very different question if it turned out that a clinic authorized escorts to speak about abortion inside the buffer zones. See post, at 1鈥2 (Alito, J., concurring in judgment). In that case, the escorts would not seem to be violating the Act because the speech would be within the scope of their employment.[3] The Act鈥檚 exemption for clinic employees would then facilitate speech on only one side of the abortion debate鈥攁 clear form of viewpoint discrimination that would support an as-applied challenge to the buffer zone at that clinic. But the record before us contains insufficient evidence to show that the exemption operates in this way at any of the clinics, perhaps because the clinics do not want to doom the Act by allowing their employees to speak about abortion within the buffer zones.[4]
We thus conclude that the Act is neither content nor viewpoint based and therefore need not be analyzed under strict scrutiny.
IV
Even though the Act is content neutral, it still must be 鈥渘arrowly tailored to serve a significant governmental interest.鈥 Ward, 491 U. S., at 796 (internal quotation marks omitted). The tailoring requirement does not sim-ply guard against an impermissible desire to censor. The government may attempt to suppress speech not only because it disagrees with the message being expressed, but also for mere convenience. Where certain speech is associated with particular problems, silencing the speech is sometimes the path of least resistance. But by demanding a close fit between ends and means, the tailoring requirement prevents the government from too readily 鈥渟acrific[ing] speech for efficiency.鈥 Riley v. National Federation of Blind of N. C., Inc., 487 U. S. 781, 795 (1988) .
For a content-neutral time, place, or manner regulation to be narrowly tailored, it must not 鈥渂urden substantially more speech than is necessary to further the government鈥檚 legitimate interests.鈥 Ward, 491 U. S., at 799. Such a regulation, unlike a content-based restriction of speech, 鈥渘eed not be the least restrictive or least intrusive means of鈥 serving the government鈥檚 interests. Id., at 798. But the government still 鈥渕ay not regulate expression in such a manner that a substantial portion of the burden on speech does not serve to advance its goals.鈥 Id., at 799.
A
As noted, respondents claim that the Act promotes 鈥減ublic safety, patient access to healthcare, and the unobstructed use of public sidewalks and roadways.鈥 Brief for Respondents 27. Petitioners do not dispute the significance of these interests. We have, moreover, previously recognized the legitimacy of the government鈥檚 interests in 鈥渆nsuring public safety and order, promoting the free flow of traffic on streets and sidewalks, protecting property rights, and protecting a woman鈥檚 freedom to seek pregnancy-related services.鈥 Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of Western N. Y., 519 U. S. 357, 376 (1997) . See also Madsen v. Women鈥檚 Health Center, Inc., 512 U. S. 753 鈥768 (1994). The buffer zones clearly serve these interests.
At the same time, the buffer zones impose serious burdens on petitioners鈥 speech. At each of the three Planned Parenthood clinics where petitioners attempt to counsel patients, the zones carve out a significant portion of the adjacent public sidewalks, pushing petitioners well back from the clinics鈥 entrances and driveways. The zones thereby compromise petitioners鈥 ability to initiate the close, personal conversations that they view as essential to 鈥渟idewalk counseling.鈥
For example, in uncontradicted testimony, McCullen explained that she often cannot distinguish patients from passersby outside the Boston clinic in time to initiate a conversation before they enter the buffer zone. App. 135. And even when she does manage to begin a discussion outside the zone, she must stop abruptly at its painted border, which she believes causes her to appear 鈥渦ntrustworthy鈥 or 鈥渟uspicious.鈥 Id., at 135, 152. Given these limitations, McCullen is often reduced to raising her voice at patients from outside the zone鈥攁 mode of communication sharply at odds with the compassionate message she wishes to convey. Id., at 133, 152鈥153. Clark gave similar testimony about her experience at the Worcester clinic. Id., at 243鈥244.
These burdens on petitioners鈥 speech have clearly taken their toll. Although McCullen claims that she has persuaded about 80 women not to terminate their pregnancies since the 2007 amendment, App. to Pet. for Cert. 42a, she also says that she reaches 鈥渇ar fewer people鈥 than she did before the amendment, App. 137. Zarrella reports an even more precipitous decline in her success rate: She estimated having about 100 successful interactions over the years before the 2007 amendment, but not a single one since. Id., at 180. And as for the Worcester clinic, Clark testified that 鈥渙nly one woman out of 100 will make the effort to walk across [the street] to speak with [her].鈥 Id., at 217.
The buffer zones have also made it substantially more difficult for petitioners to distribute literature to arriving patients. As explained, because petitioners in Boston cannot readily identify patients before they enter the zone, they often cannot approach them in time to place literature near their hands鈥攖he most effective means of getting the patients to accept it. Id., at 179. In Worcester and Springfield, the zones have pushed petitioners so far back from the clinics鈥 driveways that they can no longer even attempt to offer literature as drivers turn into the parking lots. Id., at 213, 218, 252鈥253. In short, the Act operates to deprive petitioners of their two primary methods of communicating with patients.
The Court of Appeals and respondents are wrong to downplay these burdens on petitioners鈥 speech. As the Court of Appeals saw it, the Constitution does not accord 鈥渟pecial protection鈥 to close conversations or 鈥渉andbilling.鈥 571 F. 3d, at 180. But while the First Amendment does not guarantee a speaker the right to any particular form of expression, some forms鈥攕uch as normal conversation and leafletting on a public sidewalk鈥攈ave historically been more closely associated with the transmission of ideas than others.
In the context of petition campaigns, we have observed that 鈥渙ne-on-one communication鈥 is 鈥渢he most effective, fundamental, and perhaps economical avenue of political discourse.鈥 Meyer v. Grant, 486 U. S. 414, 424 (1988) . See also Schenck, supra, at 377 (invalidating a 鈥渇loating鈥 buffer zone around people entering an abortion clinic partly on the ground that it prevented protestors 鈥渇rom communicating a message from a normal conversational distance or handing leaflets to people entering or leaving the clinics who are walking on the public sidewalks鈥). And 鈥渉anding out leaflets in the advocacy of a politically controversial viewpoint . . . is the essence of First Amendment expression鈥; 鈥淸n]o form of speech is entitled to greater constitutional protection.鈥 McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm鈥檔, 514 U. S. 334, 347 (1995) . See also Schenck, supra, at 377 (鈥淟eafletting and commenting on matters of public concern are classic forms of speech that lie at the heart of the First Amendment鈥). When the government makes it more difficult to engage in these modes of communication, it imposes an especially significant First Amendment burden.[5]
Respondents also emphasize that the Act does not prevent petitioners from engaging in various forms of 鈥減rotest鈥濃攕uch as chanting slogans and displaying signs鈥攐utside the buffer zones. Brief for Respondents 50鈥54. That misses the point. Petitioners are not protestors. They seek not merely to express their opposition to abortion, but to inform women of various alternatives and to provide help in pursuing them. Petitioners believe that they can accomplish this objective only through personal, caring, consensual conversations. And for good reason: It is easier to ignore a strained voice or a waving hand than a direct greeting or an outstretched arm. While the record indicates that petitioners have been able to have a number of quiet conversations outside the buffer zones, respondents have not refuted petitioners鈥 testimony that the conversations have been far less frequent and far less successful since the buffer zones were instituted. It is thus no answer to say that petitioners can still be 鈥渟een and heard鈥 by women within the buffer zones. Id., at 51鈥53. If all that the women can see and hear are vociferous opponents of abortion, then the buffer zones have effectively stifled petitioners鈥 message.
Finally, respondents suggest that, at the Worcester and Springfield clinics, petitioners are prevented from communicating with patients not by the buffer zones but by the fact that most patients arrive by car and park in the clinics鈥 private lots. Id., at 52. It is true that the layout of the two clinics would prevent petitioners from approaching the clinics鈥 doorways, even without the buffer zones. But petitioners do not claim a right to trespass on the clinics鈥 property. They instead claim a right to stand on the public sidewalks by the driveway as cars turn into the parking lot. Before the buffer zones, they could do so. Now they must stand a substantial distance away. The Act alone is responsible for that restriction on their ability to convey their message.
B
1
The buffer zones burden substantially more speech than necessary to achieve the Commonwealth鈥檚 asserted interests. At the outset, we note that the Act is truly exceptional: Respondents and their amici identify no other State with a law that creates fixed buffer zones around abortion clinics.[6] That of course does not mean that the law is invalid. It does, however, raise concern that the Commonwealth has too readily forgone options that could serve its interests just as well, without substantially burdening the kind of speech in which petitioners wish to engage.
That is the case here. The Commonwealth鈥檚 interests include ensuring public safety outside abortion clinics, preventing harassment and intimidation of patients and clinic staff, and combating deliberate obstruction of clinic entrances. The Act itself contains a separate provision, subsection (e)鈥攗nchallenged by petitioners鈥攖hat prohibits much of this conduct. That provision subjects to criminal punishment 鈥淸a]ny person who knowingly obstructs, detains, hinders, impedes or blocks another person鈥檚 entry to or exit from a reproductive health care facility.鈥 Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, 搂120E陆(e).[7] If Massachusetts determines that broader prohibitions along the same lines are necessary, it could enact legislation similar to the federal Freedom of Access to Clinic Entrances Act of 1994 (FACE Act), 18 U. S. C. 搂248(a)(1), which subjects to both criminal and civil penalties anyone who 鈥渂y force or threat of force or by physical obstruction, intentionally injures, intimidates or interferes with or attempts to injure, intimidate or interfere with any person because that person is or has been, or in order to intimidate such person or any other person or any class of persons from, obtaining or providing reproductive health services.鈥 Some dozen other States have done so. See Brief for State of New York et al. as Amici Curiae 13, and n. 6. If the Commonwealth is particularly concerned about harassment, it could also consider an ordinance such as the one adopted in New York City that not only prohibits obstructing access to a clinic, but also makes it a crime 鈥渢o follow and harass another person within 15 feet of the premises of a reproductive health care facility.鈥 N. Y. C. Admin. Code 搂8鈥803(a)(3) (2014).[8]
The Commonwealth points to a substantial public safety risk created when protestors obstruct driveways leading to the clinics. See App. 18, 41, 51, 88鈥89, 99, 118鈥119. That is, however, an example of its failure to look to less intrusive means of addressing its concerns. Any such obstruction can readily be addressed through existing local ordinances. See, e.g., Worcester, Mass., Revised Ordinances of 2008, ch. 12, 搂25(b) (鈥淣o person shall stand, or place any obstruction of any kind, upon any street, sidewalk or crosswalk in such a manner as to obstruct a free passage for travelers thereon鈥); Boston, Mass., Municipal Code, ch. 16鈥41.2(d) (2013) (鈥淣o person shall solicit while walking on, standing on or going into any street or highway used for motor vehicle travel, or any area appurtenant thereto (including medians, shoulder areas, bicycle lanes, ramps and exit ramps)鈥).
All of the foregoing measures are, of course, in addition to available generic criminal statutes forbidding assault, breach of the peace, trespass, vandalism, and the like.
In addition, subsection (e) of the Act, the FACE Act, and the New York City anti-harassment ordinance are all enforceable not only through criminal prosecutions but also through public and private civil actions for injunctions and other equitable relief. See Mass. Gen. Laws 搂120E陆(f); 18 U. S. C. 搂248(c)(1); N. Y. C. Admin. Code 搂搂8鈥804, 8鈥805. We have previously noted the First Amendment virtues of targeted injunctions as alternatives to broad, prophylactic measures. Such an injunction 鈥渞egulates the activities, and perhaps the speech, of a group,鈥 but only 鈥渂ecause of the group鈥檚 past actions in the context of a specific dispute between real parties.鈥 Madsen, 512 U. S., at 762 (emphasis added). Moreover, given the equitable nature of injunctive relief, courts can tailor a remedy to ensure that it restricts no more speech than necessary. See, e.g., id., at 770; Schenck, 519 U. S., at 380鈥381. In short, injunctive relief focuses on the precise individuals and the precise conduct causing a particular problem. The Act, by contrast, categorically excludes non-exempt individuals from the buffer zones, unnecessarily sweeping in innocent individuals and their speech.
The Commonwealth also asserts an interest in preventing congestion in front of abortion clinics. According to respondents, even when individuals do not deliberately obstruct access to clinics, they can inadvertently do so simply by gathering in large numbers. But the Commonwealth could address that problem through more targeted means. Some localities, for example, have ordinances that require crowds blocking a clinic entrance to disperse when ordered to do so by the police, and that forbid the individuals to reassemble within a certain distance of the clinic for a certain period. See Brief for State of New York et al. as Amici Curiae 14鈥15, and n. 10. We upheld a similar law forbidding three or more people 鈥 鈥榯o congregate within 500 feet of [a foreign embassy], and refuse to disperse after having been ordered so to do by the police,鈥 鈥 Boos, 485 U. S., at 316 (quoting D. C. Code 搂22鈥1115 (1938))鈥攁n order the police could give only when they 鈥 鈥榬easonably believe[d] that a threat to the security or peace of the embassy [was] present,鈥 鈥 485 U. S., at 330 (quoting Finzer v. Barry, 798 F. 2d 1450, 1471 (CADC 1986)).
And to the extent the Commonwealth argues that even these types of laws are ineffective, it has another problem. The portions of the record that respondents cite to support the anticongestion interest pertain mainly to one place at one time: the Boston Planned Parenthood clinic on Saturday mornings. App. 69鈥71, 88鈥89, 96, 123. Respondents point us to no evidence that individuals regularly gather at other clinics, or at other times in Boston, in sufficiently large groups to obstruct access. For a problem shown to arise only once a week in one city at one clinic, creating 35-foot buffer zones at every clinic across the Commonwealth is hardly a narrowly tailored solution.
The point is not that Massachusetts must enact all or even any of the proposed measures discussed above. The point is instead that the Commonwealth has available to it a variety of approaches that appear capable of serving its interests, without excluding individuals from areas historically open for speech and debate.
2
Respondents have but one reply: 鈥淲e have tried other approaches, but they do not work.鈥 Respondents emphasize the history in Massachusetts of obstruction at abortion clinics, and the Commonwealth鈥檚 allegedly failed attempts to combat such obstruction with injunctions and individual prosecutions. They also point to the Commonwealth鈥檚 experience under the 2000 version of the Act, during which the police found it difficult to enforce the six-foot no-approach zones given the 鈥渇renetic鈥 activity in front of clinic entrances. Brief for Respondents 43. According to respondents, this history shows that Massachusetts has tried less restrictive alternatives to the buffer zones, to no avail.
We cannot accept that contention. Although respondents claim that Massachusetts 鈥渢ried other laws already on the books,鈥 id., at 41, they identify not a single prosecution brought under those laws within at least the last 17 years. And while they also claim that the Commonwealth 鈥渢ried injunctions,鈥 ibid., the last injunctions they cite date to the 1990s, see id., at 42 (citing Planned Parenthood League of Mass., Inc. v. Bell, 424 Mass. 573, 677 N. E. 2d 204 (1997); Planned Parenthood League of Mass., Inc. v. Operation Rescue, 406 Mass. 701, 550 N. E. 2d 1361 (1990)). In short, the Commonwealth has not shown that it seriously undertook to address the problem with less intrusive tools readily available to it. Nor has it shown that it considered different methods that other jurisdictions have found effective.
Respondents contend that the alternatives we have discussed suffer from two defects: First, given the 鈥渨idespread鈥 nature of the problem, it is simply not 鈥減racticable鈥 to rely on individual prosecutions and injunctions. Brief for Respondents 45. But far from being 鈥渨idespread,鈥 the problem appears from the record to be limited principally to the Boston clinic on Saturday mornings. Moreover, by their own account, the police appear per-fectly capable of singling out lawbreakers. The legislative testimony preceding the 2007 Act revealed substantial police and video monitoring at the clinics, especially when large gatherings were anticipated. Captain Evans testified that his officers are so familiar with the scene outside the Boston clinic that they 鈥渒now all the players down there.鈥 App. 69. And Attorney General Coakley relied on video surveillance to show legislators conduct she thought was 鈥渃learly against the law.鈥 Id., at 78. If Commonwealth officials can compile an extensive record of obstruction and harassment to support their preferred legislation, we do not see why they cannot do the same to support injunctions and prosecutions against those who might deliberately flout the law.
The second supposed defect in the alternatives we have identified is that laws like subsection (e) of the Act and the federal FACE Act require a showing of intentional or deliberate obstruction, intimidation, or harassment, which is often difficult to prove. Brief for Respondents 45鈥47. As Captain Evans predicted in his legislative testimony, fixed buffer zones would 鈥渕ake our job so much easier.鈥 App. 68.
Of course they would. But that is not enough to satisfy the First Amendment. To meet the requirement of narrow tailoring, the government must demonstrate that alternative measures that burden substantially less speech would fail to achieve the government鈥檚 interests, not simply that the chosen route is easier. A painted line on the sidewalk is easy to enforce, but the prime objective of the First Amendment is not efficiency. In any case, we do not think that showing intentional obstruction is nearly so difficult in this context as respondents suggest. To determine whether a protestor intends to block access to a clinic, a police officer need only order him to move. If he refuses, then there is no question that his continued conduct is knowing or intentional.
For similar reasons, respondents鈥 reliance on our decision in Burson v. Freeman is misplaced. There, we upheld a state statute that established 100-foot buffer zones outside polling places on election day within which no one could display or distribute campaign materials or solicit votes. 504 U. S., at 193鈥194. We approved the buffer zones as a valid prophylactic measure, noting that existing 鈥淸i]ntimidation and interference laws fall short of serving a State鈥檚 compelling interests because they 鈥榙eal with only the most blatant and specific attempts鈥 to impede elections.鈥 Id., at 206鈥207 (quoting Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1, 28 (1976) (per curiam)). Such laws were insufficient because 鈥淸v]oter intimidation and election fraud are . . . difficult to detect.鈥 Burson, 504 U. S., at 208. Obstruction of abortion clinics and harassment of patients, by contrast, are anything but subtle.
We also noted in Burson that under state law, 鈥渓aw enforcement officers generally are barred from the vicinity of the polls to avoid any appearance of coercion in the electoral process,鈥 with the result that 鈥渕any acts of interference would go undetected.鈥 Id., at 207. Not so here. Again, the police maintain a significant presence outside Massachusetts abortion clinics. The buffer zones in Burson were justified because less restrictive measures were inadequate. Respondents have not shown that to be the case here.
Given the vital First Amendment interests at stake, it is not enough for Massachusetts simply to say that other approaches have not worked.[9]
*鈥冣赌*鈥冣赌*
Petitioners wish to converse with their fellow citizens about an important subject on the public streets and sidewalks鈥攕ites that have hosted discussions about the issues of the day throughout history. Respondents assert undeniably significant interests in maintaining public safety on those same streets and sidewalks, as well as in preserving access to adjacent healthcare facilities. But here the Commonwealth has pursued those interests by the extreme step of closing a substantial portion of a traditional public forum to all speakers. It has done so without seriously addressing the problem through alternatives that leave the forum open for its time-honored purposes. The Commonwealth may not do that consistent with the First Amendment.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the First Circuit is reversed, and the case is remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered.
Notes
[1] The zone could have extended an additional 21 feet in width under the Act. Only the smaller area was marked off, however, so only that area has legal effect. See Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, 搂120E陆(c).
[2] A different analysis would of course be required if the government property at issue were not a traditional public forum but instead 鈥渁 forum that is limited to use by certain groups or dedicated solely to the discussion of certain subjects.鈥 v. , .
[3] Less than two weeks after the instant litigation was initiated, the Massachusetts Attorney General鈥檚 Office issued a guidance letter clarifying the application of the four exemptions. The letter interpreted the exemptions as not permitting clinic employees or agents, municipal employees or agents, or individuals passing by clinics 鈥渢o express their views about abortion or to engage in any other partisan speech within the buffer zone.鈥 App. 93, 93鈥94. While this interpretation supports our conclusion that the employee exemption does not render the Act viewpoint based, we do not consider it in our analysis because it appears to the scope of the Act鈥攁 criminal statute鈥攔ather than to adopt a 鈥 鈥榣imiting construction.鈥 鈥 v. , (quoting v. , , n. 5 (1982)).
[4] Of course we do not hold that 鈥淸s]peech restrictions favoring one viewpoint over another are not content based unless it can be shown that the favored viewpoint has actually been expressed.鈥 ,at 13. We instead apply an uncontroversial principle of constitutional adjudication: that a plaintiff generally cannot prevail on an challenge without showing that the law has in fact been (or is sufficiently likely to be) unconstitutionally to him. Specifically, when someone challenges a law as viewpoint discriminatory but it is not clear from the face of the law which speakers will be allowed to speak, he must show that he was prevented from speaking while someone espousing another viewpoint was permitted to do so. can decry this analysis as 鈥渁stonishing鈥 only by quoting a sentence that is explicitly limited to as-applied challenges and treating it as relevant to facial challenges.
[5] As a leading historian has noted:
[6] do identify five localities with laws similar to the Act here. Brief for State of New York et al. as 14, n. 7.
[7] Massachusetts also has a separate law prohibiting similar kinds of conduct at any 鈥渕edical facility,鈥 though that law, unlike the Act, requires explicit notice before any penalty may be imposed. Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 266, 搂120E.
[8] We do not 鈥済ive [our] approval鈥 to this or any of the other alternatives we discuss. ,at 4. We merely suggest that a law like the New York City ordinance could in principle constitute a permissible alternative. Whether such a law would pass constitutional muster would depend on a number of other factors, such as whether the term 鈥渉arassment鈥 had been authoritatively construed to avoid vagueness and overbreadth problems of the sort noted by .
[9] Because we find that the Act is not narrowly tailored, we need not consider whether the Act leaves open ample alternative channels of communication. Nor need we consider petitioners鈥 overbreadth challenge.