BURWELL v. HOBBY LOBBY STORES
Supreme Court Cases
573 U.S. 682 (2014)
Opinions
Majority Opinion Author
Samuel Alito
Majority Participants
Concurring Participants
Dissenting Participants
NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200 U. S. 321, 337.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
Syllabus
BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVICES, et al. v. HOBBY LOBBY STORES, INC., et al.
certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the tenth circuit
No. 13鈥354.鈥傾rgued March 25, 2014鈥擠ecided June 30, 2014
The Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993 (RFRA) prohibits the 鈥淕overnment [from] substantially burden[ing] a person鈥檚 exercise of religion even if the burden results from a rule of general applicability鈥 unless the Government 鈥渄emonstrates that application of the burden to the person鈥(1) is in furtherance of a compelling governmental interest; and (2) is the least restrictive means of furthering that compelling governmental interest.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂搂2000bb鈥1(a), (b). As amended by the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act of 2000 (RLUIPA), RFRA covers 鈥渁ny exercise of religion, whether or not compelled by, or central to, a system of religious belief.鈥 搂2000cc鈥5(7)(A).
At issue here are regulations promulgated by the Department of Health and Human Services (HHS) under the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act of 2010 (ACA), which, as relevant here, requires specified employers鈥 group health plans to furnish 鈥減reventive care and screenings鈥 for women without 鈥渁ny cost sharing requirements,鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂300gg鈥13(a)(4). Congress did not specify what types of preventive care must be covered; it authorized the Health Resources and Services Administration, a component of HHS, to decide. Ibid. Nonexempt employers are generally required to provide coverage for the 20 contraceptive methods approved by the Food and Drug Administration, including the 4 that may have the effect of preventing an already fertilized egg from developing any further by inhibiting its attachment to the uterus. Religious employers, such as churches, are exempt from this contraceptive mandate. HHS has also effectively exempted religious nonprofit organizations with religious objections to providing coverage for contraceptive services. Under this accommodation, the insurance issuer must exclude contraceptive coverage from the employer鈥檚 plan and provide plan participants with separate payments for contraceptive services without imposing any cost-sharing requirements on the employer, its insurance plan, or its employee beneficiaries.
In these cases, the owners of three closely held for-profit corporations have sincere Christian beliefs that life begins at conception and that it would violate their religion to facilitate access to contraceptive drugs or devices that operate after that point. In separate actions, they sued HHS and other federal officials and agencies (collectively HHS) under RFRA and the Free Exercise Clause, seeking to enjoin application of the contraceptive mandate insofar as it requires them to provide health coverage for the four objectionable contraceptives. In No. 13鈥356, the District Court denied the Hahns and their company鈥擟onestoga Wood Specialties鈥攁 preliminary injunction. Affirming, the Third Circuit held that a for-profit corporation could not 鈥渆ngage in religious exercise鈥 under RFRA or the First Amendment, and that the mandate imposed no requirements on the Hahns in their personal capacity. In No. 13鈥354, the Greens, their children, and their companies鈥擧obby Lobby Stores and Mardel鈥攚ere also denied a preliminary injunction, but the Tenth Circuit reversed. It held that the Greens鈥 businesses are 鈥減ersons鈥 under RFRA, and that the corporations had established a likelihood of success on their RFRA claim because the contraceptive mandate substantially burdened their exercise of religion and HHS had not demonstrated a compelling interest in enforcing the mandate against them; in the alternative, the court held that HHS had not proved that the mandate was the 鈥渓east restrictive means鈥 of furthering a compelling governmental interest.
Held: As applied to closely held corporations, the HHS regulations imposing the contraceptive mandate violate RFRA. Pp. 16鈥49.
(a) RFRA applies to regulations that govern the activities of closely held for-profit corporations like Conestoga, Hobby Lobby, and Mardel. Pp. 16鈥31.
(1) HHS argues that the companies cannot sue because they are for-profit corporations, and that the owners cannot sue because the regulations apply only to the companies, but that would leave merchants with a difficult choice: give up the right to seek judicial protection of their religious liberty or forgo the benefits of operating as corporations. RFRA鈥檚 text shows that Congress designed the statute to provide very broad protection for religious liberty and did not intend to put merchants to such a choice. It employed the familiar legal fiction of including corporations within RFRA鈥檚 definition of 鈥減ersons,鈥 but the purpose of extending rights to corporations is to protect the rights of people associated with the corporation, including shareholders, officers, and employees. Protecting the free-exercise rights of closely held corporations thus protects the religious liberty of the humans who own and control them. Pp. 16鈥19.
(2) HHS and the dissent make several unpersuasive arguments. Pp. 19鈥31.
(i) Nothing in RFRA suggests a congressional intent to depart from the Dictionary Act definition of 鈥減erson,鈥 which 鈥渋nclude[s] corporations, . . . as well as individuals.鈥 1 U. S. C. 搂1. The Court has entertained RFRA and free-exercise claims brought by nonprofit corporations. See, e.g., Gonzales v. O Centro Esp铆rita Beneficiente Uni茫o do Vegetal, 546 U.S. 418. And HHS鈥檚 concession that a nonprofit corporation can be a 鈥減erson鈥 under RFRA effectively dispatches any argument that the term does not reach for-profit corporations; no conceivable definition of 鈥減erson鈥 includes natural persons and nonprofit corporations, but not for-profit corporations. Pp. 19鈥20.
(ii) HHS and the dissent nonetheless argue that RFRA does not cover Conestoga, Hobby Lobby, and Mardel because they cannot 鈥渆xercise . . . religion.鈥 They offer no persuasive explanation for this conclusion. The corporate form alone cannot explain it because RFRA indisputably protects nonprofit corporations. And the profit-making objective of the corporations cannot explain it because the Court has entertained the free-exercise claims of individuals who were attempting to make a profit as retail merchants. Braunfeld v. Brown, 366 U.S. 599. Business practices compelled or limited by the tenets of a religious doctrine fall comfortably within the understanding of the 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 that this Court set out in Employment Div., Dept. of Human Resources of Ore. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 877. Any suggestion that for-profit corporations are incapable of exercising religion because their purpose is simply to make money flies in the face of modern corporate law. States, including those in which the plaintiff corporations were incorporated, authorize corporations to pursue any lawful purpose or business, including the pursuit of profit in conformity with the owners鈥 religious principles. Pp. 20鈥25.
(iii) Also flawed is the claim that RFRA offers no protection because it only codified pre-Smith Free Exercise Clause precedents, none of which squarely recognized free-exercise rights for for-profit corporations. First, nothing in RFRA as originally enacted suggested that its definition of 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 was meant to be tied to pre-Smith interpretations of the First Amendment. Second, if RFRA鈥檚 original text were not clear enough, the RLUIPA amendment surely dispels any doubt that Congress intended to separate the definition of the phrase from that in First Amendment case law. Third, the pre-Smith case of Gallagher v. Crown Kosher Super Market of Mass., Inc., 366 U.S. 617, suggests, if anything, that for-profit corporations can exercise religion. Finally, the results would be absurd if RFRA, a law enacted to provide very broad protection for religious liberty, merely restored this Court鈥檚 pre-Smith decisions in ossified form and restricted RFRA claims to plaintiffs who fell within a category of plaintiffs whose claims the Court had recognized before Smith. Pp. 25鈥28.
(3) Finally, HHS contends that Congress could not have wanted RFRA to apply to for-profit corporations because of the difficulty of ascertaining the 鈥渂eliefs鈥 of large, publicly traded corporations, but HHS has not pointed to any example of a publicly traded corporation asserting RFRA rights, and numerous practical restraints would likely prevent that from occurring. HHS has also provided no evidence that the purported problem of determining the sincerity of an asserted religious belief moved Congress to exclude for-profit corporations from RFRA鈥檚 protection. That disputes among the owners of corporations might arise is not a problem unique to this context. State corporate law provides a ready means for resolving any conflicts by, for example, dictating how a corporation can establish its governing structure. Courts will turn to that structure and the underlying state law in resolving disputes. Pp. 29鈥31.
(b) HHS鈥檚 contraceptive mandate substantially burdens the exercise of religion. Pp. 31鈥38.
(1) It requires the Hahns and Greens to engage in conduct that seriously violates their sincere religious belief that life begins at conception. If they and their companies refuse to provide contraceptive coverage, they face severe economic consequences: about $475 million per year for Hobby Lobby, $33 million per year for Conestoga, and $15 million per year for Mardel. And if they drop coverage altogether, they could face penalties of roughly $26 million for Hobby Lobby, $1.8 million for Conestoga, and $800,000 for Mardel. P. 32.
(2) Amici supporting HHS argue that the $2,000 per-employee penalty is less than the average cost of providing insurance, and therefore that dropping insurance coverage eliminates any substantial burden imposed by the mandate. HHS has never argued this and the Court does not know its position with respect to the argument. But even if the Court reached the argument, it would find it unpersuasive: It ignores the fact that the plaintiffs have religious reasons for providing health-insurance coverage for their employees, and it is far from clear that the net cost to the companies of providing insurance is more than the cost of dropping their insurance plans and paying the ACA penalty. Pp. 32鈥35.
(3) HHS argues that the connection between what the objecting parties must do and the end that they find to be morally wrong is too attenuated because it is the employee who will choose the coverage and contraceptive method she uses. But RFRA鈥檚 question is whether the mandate imposes a substantial burden on the objecting parties鈥 ability to conduct business in accordance with their religious beliefs. The belief of the Hahns and Greens implicates a difficult and important question of religion and moral philosophy, namely, the circumstances under which it is immoral for a person to perform an act that is innocent in itself but that has the effect of enabling or facilitating the commission of an immoral act by another. It is not for the Court to say that the religious beliefs of the plaintiffs are mistaken or unreasonable. In fact, this Court considered and rejected a nearly identical argument in Thomas v. Review Bd. of Indiana Employment Security Div., 450 U.S. 707. The Court鈥檚 鈥渘arrow function . . . is to determine鈥 whether the plaintiffs鈥 asserted religious belief reflects 鈥渁n honest conviction,鈥 id., at 716, and there is no dispute here that it does. Tilton v. Richardson, 403 U.S. 672, 689; and Board of Ed. of Central School Dist. No. 1 v. Allen, 392 U.S. 236, 248鈥249, distinguished. Pp. 35鈥38.
(c) The Court assumes that the interest in guaranteeing cost-free access to the four challenged contraceptive methods is a compelling governmental interest, but the Government has failed to show that the contraceptive mandate is the least restrictive means of furthering that interest. Pp. 38鈥49.
(1) The Court assumes that the interest in guaranteeing cost-free access to the four challenged contraceptive methods is compelling within the meaning of RFRA. Pp. 39鈥40.
(2) The Government has failed to satisfy RFRA鈥檚 least-restrictive-means standard. HHS has not shown that it lacks other means of achieving its desired goal without imposing a substantial burden on the exercise of religion. The Government could, e.g., assume the cost of providing the four contraceptives to women unable to obtain coverage due to their employers鈥 religious objections. Or it could extend the accommodation that HHS has already established for religious nonprofit organizations to non-profit employers with religious objections to the contraceptive mandate. That accommodation does not impinge on the plaintiffs鈥 religious beliefs that providing insurance coverage for the contraceptives at issue here violates their religion and it still serves HHS鈥檚 stated interests. Pp. 40鈥45.
(3) This decision concerns only the contraceptive mandate and should not be understood to hold that all insurance-coverage mandates, e.g., for vaccinations or blood transfusions, must necessarily fall if they conflict with an employer鈥檚 religious beliefs. Nor does it provide a shield for employers who might cloak illegal discrimination as a religious practice. United States v. Lee, 455 U.S. 252, which upheld the payment of Social Security taxes despite an employer鈥檚 religious objection, is not analogous. It turned primarily on the special problems associated with a national system of taxation; and if Lee were a RFRA case, the fundamental point would still be that there is no less restrictive alternative to the categorical requirement to pay taxes. Here, there is an alternative to the contraceptive mandate. Pp. 45鈥49.
No. 13鈥354, 723 F.3d 1114, affirmed; No. 13鈥356, 724 F.3d 377, reversed and remanded.
Alito, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which Roberts, C. J., and Scalia, Kennedy, and Thomas, JJ., joined. Kennedy, J., filed a concurring opinion. Ginsburg, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which Sotomayor, J., joined, and in which Breyer and Kagan, JJ., joined as to all but Part III鈥揅鈥1. Breyer and Kagan, JJ., filed a dissenting opinion.
NOTICE:鈥俆his opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the United States Reports.鈥僐eaders are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 13鈥354 and 13鈥356
_________________
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND HUMAN SERVICES, et al., PETITIONERS
v.
HOBBY LOBBY STORES, INC., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states courtof appeals for the tenth circuit
and
CONESTOGA WOOD SPECIALTIES CORPORATIONet al., PETITIONERS
v.
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND HUMAN SERVICES, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states courtof appeals for the third circuit
[June 30, 2014]
Justice Alito delivered the opinion of the Court.
We must decide in these cases whether the Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993 (RFRA), 107Stat. 1488, 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb et seq., permits the United States Department of Health and Human Services (HHS) to demand that three closely held corporations provide health-insurance coverage for methods of contraception that violate the sincerely held religious beliefs of the companies鈥 owners. We hold that the regulations that impose this obligation violate RFRA, which prohibits the Federal Government from taking any action that substantially burdens the exercise of religion unless that action constitutes the least restrictive means of serving a compelling government interest.
In holding that the HHS mandate is unlawful, we reject HHS鈥檚 argument that the owners of the companies for-feited all RFRA protection when they decided to organize their businesses as corporations rather than sole proprietorships or general partnerships. The plain terms of RFRA make it perfectly clear that Congress did not discriminate in this way against men and women who wish to run their businesses as for-profit corporations in the manner required by their religious beliefs.
Since RFRA applies in these cases, we must decide whether the challenged HHS regulations substantially burden the exercise of religion, and we hold that they do. The owners of the businesses have religious objections to abortion, and according to their religious beliefs the four contraceptive methods at issue are abortifacients. If the owners comply with the HHS mandate, they believe they will be facilitating abortions, and if they do not comply, they will pay a very heavy price鈥攁s much as $1.3 million per day, or about $475 million per year, in the case of one of the companies. If these consequences do not amount to a substantial burden, it is hard to see what would.
Under RFRA, a Government action that imposes a substantial burden on religious exercise must serve a compelling government interest, and we assume that the HHS regulations satisfy this requirement. But in order for the HHS mandate to be sustained, it must also constitute the least restrictive means of serving that interest, and the mandate plainly fails that test. There are other ways in which Congress or HHS could equally ensure that every woman has cost-free access to the particular contraceptives at issue here and, indeed, to all FDA-approved contraceptives.
In fact, HHS has already devised and implemented a system that seeks to respect the religious liberty of religious nonprofit corporations while ensuring that the employees of these entities have precisely the same access to all FDA-approved contraceptives as employees of companies whose owners have no religious objections to providing such coverage. The employees of these religious nonprofit corporations still have access to insurance coverage without cost sharing for all FDA-approved contracep-tives; and according to HHS, this system imposes no net economic burden on the insurance companies that are required to provide or secure the coverage.
Although HHS has made this system available to religious nonprofits that have religious objections to the contraceptive mandate, HHS has provided no reason why the same system cannot be made available when the owners of for-profit corporations have similar religious objections. We therefore conclude that this system constitutes an alternative that achieves all of the Government鈥檚 aims while providing greater respect for religious liberty. And under RFRA, that conclusion means that enforcement of the HHS contraceptive mandate against the objecting parties in these cases is unlawful.
As this description of our reasoning shows, our holding is very specific. We do not hold, as the principal dissent alleges, that for-profit corporations and other commercial enterprises can 鈥渙pt out of any law (saving only tax laws) they judge incompatible with their sincerely held religious beliefs.鈥 Post, at 1 (opinion of Ginsburg, J.). Nor do we hold, as the dissent implies, that such corporations have free rein to take steps that impose 鈥渄isadvantages . . . on others鈥 or that require 鈥渢he general public [to] pick up the tab.鈥 Post, at 1鈥2. And we certainly do not hold or suggest that 鈥淩FRA demands accommodation of a for-profit corporation鈥檚 religious beliefs no matter the impact that accommodation may have on . . . thousands of women employed by Hobby Lobby.鈥 Post, at 2.[1] The effect of the HHS-created accommodation on the women employed by Hobby Lobby and the other companies involved in these cases would be precisely zero. Under that accommodation, these women would still be entitled to all FDA-approved contraceptives without cost sharing.
I
A
Congress enacted RFRA in 1993 in order to provide very broad protection for religious liberty. RFRA鈥檚 enactment came three years after this Court鈥檚 decision in Employment Div., Dept. of Human Resources of Ore. v. Smith, 494 U. S. 872 (1990) , which largely repudiated the method of analyzing free-exercise claims that had been used in cases like Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U. S. 398 (1963), and Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U. S. 205 (1972) . In determining whether challenged government actions violated the Free Exercise Clause of the First Amendment, those decisions used a balancing test that took into account whether the challenged action imposed a substantial burden on the practice of religion, and if it did, whether it was needed to serve a compelling government interest. Applying this test, the Court held in Sherbert that an employee who was fired for refusing to work on her Sabbath could not be denied unemployment benefits. 374 U. S., at 408鈥409. And in Yoder, the Court held that Amish children could not be required to comply with a state law demanding that they remain in school until the age of 16 even though their religion required them to focus on uniquely Amish values and beliefs during their formative adolescent years. 406 U. S., at 210鈥211, 234鈥236.
In Smith, however, the Court rejected 鈥渢he balancing test set forth in Sherbert.鈥 494 U. S., at 883. Smith concerned two members of the Native American Church who were fired for ingesting peyote for sacramental purposes. When they sought unemployment benefits, the State of Oregon rejected their claims on the ground that consumption of peyote was a crime, but the Oregon Supreme Court, applying the Sherbert test, held that the denial of benefits violated the Free Exercise Clause. 494 U. S., at 875.
This Court then reversed, observing that use of the Sherbert test whenever a person objected on religious grounds to the enforcement of a generally applicable law 鈥渨ould open the prospect of constitutionally required religious exemptions from civic obligations of almost every conceivable kind.鈥 494 U. S., at 888. The Court therefore held that, under the First Amendment, 鈥渘eutral, generally applicable laws may be applied to religious practices even when not supported by a compelling governmental interest.鈥 City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U. S. 507, 514 (1997).
Congress responded to Smith by enacting RFRA. 鈥淸L]aws [that are] 鈥榥eutral鈥 toward religion,鈥 Congress found, 鈥渕ay burden religious exercise as surely as laws intended to interfere with religious exercise.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb(a)(2); see also 搂2000bb(a)(4). In order to ensure broad protection for religious liberty, RFRA provides that 鈥淕overnment shall not substantially burden a person鈥檚 exercise of religion even if the burden results from a rule of general applicability.鈥 搂2000bb鈥1(a).[2] If the Government substantially burdens a person鈥檚 exercise of religion, under the Act that person is entitled to an exemption from the rule unless the Government 鈥渄emonstrates that application of the burden to the person鈥(1) is in furtherance of a compelling governmental interest; and (2) is the least restrictive means of furthering that compelling governmental interest.鈥 搂2000bb鈥1(b).[3]
As enacted in 1993, RFRA applied to both the Federal Government and the States, but the constitutional authority invoked for regulating federal and state agencies differed. As applied to a federal agency, RFRA is based on the enumerated power that supports the particular agency鈥檚 work,[4] but in attempting to regulate the States and their subdivisions, Congress relied on its power under Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment to enforce the First Amendment. 521 U. S., at 516鈥517. In City of Boerne, however, we held that Congress had overstepped its Section 5 authority because 鈥淸t]he stringent test RFRA demands鈥 鈥渇ar exceed[ed] any pattern or practice of unconstitutional conduct under the Free Exercise Clause as interpreted in Smith.鈥 Id., at 533鈥534. See also id., at 532.
Following our decision in City of Boerne, Congress passed the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act of 2000 (RLUIPA), 114Stat. 803, 42 U. S. C. 搂2000cc et seq. That statute, enacted under Congress鈥檚 Commerce and Spending Clause powers, imposes the same general test as RFRA but on a more limited category of governmental actions. See Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U. S. 709 鈥716 (2005). And, what is most relevant for present purposes, RLUIPA amended RFRA鈥檚 definition of the 鈥渆xercise of religion.鈥 See 搂2000bb鈥2(4) (importing RLUIPA definition). Before RLUIPA, RFRA鈥檚 definition made reference to the First Amendment. See 搂2000bb鈥2(4) (1994 ed.) (defining 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 as 鈥渢he exercise of religion under the First Amendment鈥). In RLUIPA, in an obvious effort to effect a complete separation from First Amendment case law, Congress deleted the reference to the First Amendment and defined the 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 to include 鈥渁ny exercise of religion, whether or not compelled by, or central to, a system of religious belief.鈥 搂2000cc鈥5(7)(A). And Congress mandated that this concept 鈥渂e construed in favor of a broad protection of religious exercise, to the maximum extent permitted by the terms of this chapter and the Constitution.鈥 搂2000cc鈥3(g).[5]
B
At issue in these cases are HHS regulations promul-gated under the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act of 2010 (ACA), 124Stat. 119. ACA generally requires employers with 50 or more full-time employees to offer鈥渁 group health plan or group health insurance coverage鈥 that provides 鈥渕inimum essential coverage.鈥 26 U. S. C. 搂5000A(f)(2); 搂搂4980H(a), (c)(2). Any covered employer that does not provide such coverage must pay a substantial price. Specifically, if a covered employer provides group health insurance but its plan fails to comply with ACA鈥檚 group-health-plan requirements, the employer may be required to pay $100 per day for each affected 鈥渋ndividual.鈥 搂搂4980D(a)鈥(b). And if the employer decides to stop providing health insurance altogether and at least one full-time employee enrolls in a health plan and qualifies for a subsidy on one of the government-run ACA exchanges, the employer must pay $2,000 per year for each of its full-time employees. 搂搂4980H(a), (c)(1).
Unless an exception applies, ACA requires an employer鈥檚 group health plan or group-health-insurance coverage to furnish 鈥減reventive care and screenings鈥 for women without 鈥渁ny cost sharing requirements.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂300gg鈥13(a)(4). Congress itself, however, did not specify what types of preventive care must be covered. Instead, Congress authorized the Health Resources and Services Administration (HRSA), a component of HHS, to make that important and sensitive decision. Ibid. The HRSA in turn consulted the Institute of Medicine, a nonprofit group of volunteer advisers, in determining which preventive services to require. See 77 Fed. Reg. 8725鈥8726 (2012).
In August 2011, based on the Institute鈥檚 recommendations, the HRSA promulgated the Women鈥檚 Preventive Services Guidelines. See id., at 8725鈥8726, and n. 1; online at http://hrsa.gov/womensguidelines (all Internet materials as visited June 26, 2014, and available in Clerk of Court鈥檚 case file). The Guidelines provide that nonexempt employers are generally required to provide 鈥渃overage, without cost sharing鈥 for 鈥淸a]ll Food and Drug Ad-ministration [(FDA)] approved contraceptive methods, sterilization procedures, and patient education and counseling.鈥 77 Fed. Reg. 8725 (internal quotation marks omitted). Although many of the required, FDA-approved methods of contraception work by preventing the fertilization of an egg, four of those methods (those specifically at issue in these cases) may have the effect of preventing an already fertilized egg from developing any further by inhibiting its attachment to the uterus. See Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥354, pp. 9鈥10, n. 4;[6] FDA, Birth Control: Medicines to Help You.[7]
HHS also authorized the HRSA to establish exemptions from the contraceptive mandate for 鈥渞eligious employers.鈥 45 CFR 搂147.131(a). That category encompasses 鈥渃hurches, their integrated auxiliaries, and conventions or associ-ations of churches,鈥 as well as 鈥渢he exclusively religious activities of any religious order.鈥 See ibid (citing 26 U. S. C. 搂搂6033(a)(3)(A)(i), (iii)). In its Guidelines,HRSA exempted these organizations from the requirement to cover contraceptive services. See http://hrsa.gov/womensguidelines.
In addition, HHS has effectively exempted certain religious nonprofit organizations, described under HHS regulations as 鈥渆ligible organizations,鈥 from the contraceptive mandate. See 45 CFR 搂147.131(b); 78 Fed. Reg. 39874 (2013). An 鈥渆ligible organization鈥 means a nonprofit organization that 鈥渉olds itself out as a religious organi-zation鈥 and 鈥渙pposes providing coverage for some or all of any contraceptive services required to be covered . . . on account of religious objections.鈥 45 CFR 搂147.131(b). To qualify for this accommodation, an employer must certify that it is such an organization. 搂147.131(b)(4). When a group-health-insurance issuer receives notice that one of its clients has invoked this provision, the issuer must then exclude contraceptive coverage from the employer鈥檚 plan and provide separate payments for contraceptive services for plan participants without imposing any cost-sharing requirements on the eligible organization, its insurance plan, or its employee beneficiaries. 搂147.131(c).[8] Al-though this procedure requires the issuer to bear the cost of these services, HHS has determined that this obligation will not impose any net expense on issuers because its cost will be less than or equal to the cost savings resulting from the services. 78 Fed. Reg. 39877.[9]
In addition to these exemptions for religious organizations, ACA exempts a great many employers from most of its coverage requirements. Employers providing 鈥済randfathered health plans鈥濃攖hose that existed prior to March 23, 2010, and that have not made specified changes after that date鈥攏eed not comply with many of the Act鈥檚 requirements, including the contraceptive mandate. 42 U. S. C. 搂搂18011(a), (e). And employers with fewer than 50 employees are not required to provide health insurance at all. 26 U. S. C. 搂4980H(c)(2).
All told, the contraceptive mandate 鈥減resently does not apply to tens of millions of people.鈥 723 F. 3d 1114, 1143 (CA10 2013). This is attributable, in large part, to grandfathered health plans: Over one-third of the 149 million nonelderly people in America with employer-sponsored health plans were enrolled in grandfathered plans in 2013. Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥354, at 53; Kaiser Family Foundation & Health Research & Educational Trust, Employer Health Benefits, 2013 Annual Survey 43, 221.[10] The count for employees working for firms that do not have to provide insurance at all because they employ fewer than 50 employees is 34 million workers. See The Whitehouse, Health Reform for Small Businesses: The Affordable Care Act Increases Choice and Saving Money for Small Businesses 1.[11]
II
A
Norman and Elizabeth Hahn and their three sons are devout members of the Mennonite Church, a Christian denomination. The Mennonite Church opposes abortion and believes that 鈥淸t]he fetus in its earliest stages . . . shares humanity with those who conceived it.鈥[12]
Fifty years ago, Norman Hahn started a wood-working business in his garage, and since then, this company, Conestoga Wood Specialties, has grown and now has 950 employees. Conestoga is organized under Pennsylvania law as a for-profit corporation. The Hahns exercise sole ownership of the closely held business; they control its board of directors and hold all of its voting shares. One of the Hahn sons serves as the president and CEO.
The Hahns believe that they are required to run their business 鈥渋n accordance with their religious beliefs and moral principles.鈥 917 F. Supp. 2d 394, 402 (ED Pa. 2013). To that end, the company鈥檚 mission, as they see it, is to 鈥渙perate in a professional environment founded upon the highest ethical, moral, and Christian principles.鈥 Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). The company鈥檚 鈥淰ision and Values Statements鈥 affirms that Conestoga endeavors to 鈥渆nsur[e] a reasonable profit in [a] manner that reflects [the Hahns鈥橾 Christian heritage.鈥 App. in No. 13鈥356, p. 94 (complaint).
As explained in Conestoga鈥檚 board-adopted 鈥淪tatement on the Sanctity of Human Life,鈥 the Hahns believe that 鈥渉uman life begins at conception.鈥 724 F. 3d 377, 382, and n. 5 (CA3 2013) (internal quotation marks omitted). It is therefore 鈥渁gainst [their] moral conviction to be involved in the termination of human life鈥 after conception, which they believe is a 鈥渟in against God to which they are held accountable.鈥 Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). The Hahns have accordingly excluded from the group-health-insurance plan they offer to their employees certain contraceptive methods that they consider to be abortifacients. Id., at 382.
The Hahns and Conestoga sued HHS and other federal officials and agencies under RFRA and the Free Exercise Clause of the First Amendment, seeking to enjoin application of ACA鈥檚 contraceptive mandate insofar as it requires them to provide health-insurance coverage for four FDA-approved contraceptives that may operate after the fertilization of an egg.[13] These include two forms of emergency contraception commonly called 鈥渕orning after鈥 pills and two types of intrauterine devices.[14]
In opposing the requirement to provide coverage for the contraceptives to which they object, the Hahns argued that 鈥渋t is immoral and sinful for [them] to intentionally participate in, pay for, facilitate, or otherwise support these drugs.鈥 Ibid. The District Court denied a preliminary injunction, see 917 F. Supp. 2d, at 419, and the Third Circuit affirmed in a divided opinion, holding that 鈥渇or-profit, secular corporations cannot engage in religious exercise鈥 within the meaning of RFRA or the First Amendment. 724 F. 3d, at 381. The Third Circuit also rejected the claims brought by the Hahns themselves because it concluded that the HHS 鈥淸m]andate does not impose any requirements on the Hahns鈥 in their personal capacity. Id., at 389.
B
David and Barbara Green and their three children are Christians who own and operate two family businesses. Forty-five years ago, David Green started an arts-and-crafts store that has grown into a nationwide chain called Hobby Lobby. There are now 500 Hobby Lobby stores, and the company has more than 13,000 employees. 723 F. 3d, at 1122. Hobby Lobby is organized as a for-profit corporation under Oklahoma law.
One of David鈥檚 sons started an affiliated business, Mardel, which operates 35 Christian bookstores and employs close to 400 people. Ibid. Mardel is also organized as a for-profit corporation under Oklahoma law.
Though these two businesses have expanded over the years, they remain closely held, and David, Barbara, and their children retain exclusive control of both companies. Ibid. David serves as the CEO of Hobby Lobby, and his three children serve as the president, vice president, and vice CEO. See Brief for Respondents in No. 13鈥354, p. 8.[15]
Hobby Lobby鈥檚 statement of purpose commits the Greens to 鈥淸h]onoring the Lord in all [they] do by operating the company in a manner consistent with Biblical principles.鈥 App. in No. 13鈥354, pp. 134鈥135 (complaint). Each family member has signed a pledge to run the businesses in accordance with the family鈥檚 religious beliefs and to use the family assets to support Christian ministries. 723 F. 3d, at 1122. In accordance with those commitments, Hobby Lobby and Mardel stores close on Sundays, even though the Greens calculate that they lose millions in sales annually by doing so. Id., at 1122; App. in No. 13鈥354, at 136鈥137. The businesses refuse to engage in profitable transactions that facilitate or promote alcohol use; they contribute profits to Christian missionaries and ministries; and they buy hundreds of full-page newspaper ads inviting people to 鈥渒now Jesus as Lord and Savior.鈥 Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted).
Like the Hahns, the Greens believe that life begins at conception and that it would violate their religion to facilitate access to contraceptive drugs or devices that operate after that point. 723 F. 3d, at 1122. They specifically object to the same four contraceptive methods as the Hahns and, like the Hahns, they have no objection to the other 16 FDA-approved methods of birth control. Id., at 1125. Although their group-health-insurance plan predates the enactment of ACA, it is not a grandfathered plan because Hobby Lobby elected not to retain grandfathered status before the contraceptive mandate was proposed. Id., at 1124.
The Greens, Hobby Lobby, and Mardel sued HHS and other federal agencies and officials to challenge the contraceptive mandate under RFRA and the Free Exercise Clause.[16] The District Court denied a preliminary injunction, see 870 F. Supp. 2d 1278 (WD Okla. 2012), and the plaintiffs appealed, moving for initial en banc consideration. The Tenth Circuit granted that motion and reversed in a divided opinion. Contrary to the conclusion of the Third Circuit, the Tenth Circuit held that the Greens鈥 two for-profit businesses are 鈥減ersons鈥 within the meaning of RFRA and therefore may bring suit under that law.
The court then held that the corporations had established a likelihood of success on their RFRA claim. 723 F. 3d, at 1140鈥1147. The court concluded that the contraceptive mandate substantially burdened the exercise of religion by requiring the companies to choose between 鈥渃ompromis[ing] their religious beliefs鈥 and paying a heavy fee鈥攅ither 鈥渃lose to $475 million more in taxes every year鈥 if they simply refused to provide coverage for the contraceptives at issue, or 鈥渞oughly $26 million鈥 annually if they 鈥渄rop[ped] health-insurance benefits for all employees.鈥 Id., at 1141.
The court next held that HHS had failed to demonstrate a compelling interest in enforcing the mandate against the Greens鈥 businesses and, in the alternative, that HHS had failed to prove that enforcement of the mandate was the 鈥渓east restrictive means鈥 of furthering the Government鈥檚 asserted interests. Id., at 1143鈥1144 (emphasis deleted; internal quotation marks omitted). After concluding that the companies had 鈥渄emonstrated irreparable harm,鈥 the court reversed and remanded for the District Court to consider the remaining factors of the preliminary-injunction test. Id., at 1147.[17]
We granted certiorari. 571 U. S. ___ (2013).
III
A
RFRA prohibits the 鈥淕overnment [from] substantially burden[ing] a person鈥檚 exercise of religion even if the burden results from a rule of general applicability鈥 unless the Government 鈥渄emonstrates that application of the burden to the person鈥(1) is in furtherance of a compelling governmental interest; and (2) is the least restrictive means of furthering that compelling governmental interest.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂搂2000bb鈥1(a), (b) (emphasis added). The first question that we must address is whether this provision applies to regulations that govern the activities of for-profit corporations like Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel.
HHS contends that neither these companies nor their owners can even be heard under RFRA. According to HHS, the companies cannot sue because they seek to make a profit for their owners, and the owners cannotbe heard because the regulations, at least as a formal mat-ter, apply only to the companies and not to the ownersas individuals. HHS鈥檚 argument would have dramatic consequences.
Consider this Court鈥檚 decision in Braunfeld v. Brown, 366 U. S. 599 (1961) (plurality opinion). In that case, five Orthodox Jewish merchants who ran small retail businesses in Philadelphia challenged a Pennsylvania Sunday closing law as a violation of the Free Exercise Clause. Because of their faith, these merchants closed their shops on Saturday, and they argued that requiring them to remain shut on Sunday threatened them with financial ruin. The Court entertained their claim (although it ruled against them on the merits), and if a similar claim were raised today under RFRA against a jurisdiction still subject to the Act (for example, the District of Columbia, see 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb鈥2(2)), the merchants would be entitled to be heard. According to HHS, however, if these merchants chose to incorporate their businesses鈥攚ith-out in any way changing the size or nature of their businesses鈥攖hey would forfeit all RFRA (and free-exercise) rights. HHS would put these merchants to a difficult choice: either give up the right to seek judicial protection of their religious liberty or forgo the benefits, available to their competitors, of operating as corporations.
As we have seen, RFRA was designed to provide very broad protection for religious liberty. By enacting RFRA, Congress went far beyond what this Court has held is constitutionally required.[18] Is there any reason to think that the Congress that enacted such sweeping protection put small-business owners to the choice that HHS suggests? An examination of RFRA鈥檚 text, to which we turn in the next part of this opinion, reveals that Congress did no such thing.
As we will show, Congress provided protection for people like the Hahns and Greens by employing a familiar legal fiction: It included corporations within RFRA鈥檚 definition of 鈥減ersons.鈥 But it is important to keep in mind that the purpose of this fiction is to provide protection for human beings. A corporation is simply a form of organization used by human beings to achieve desired ends. An established body of law specifies the rights and obligations of the people (including shareholders, officers, and employees) who are associated with a corporation in one way or another. When rights, whether constitutional or statu-tory, are extended to corporations, the purpose is to protect the rights of these people. For example, extending Fourth Amendment protection to corporations protects the privacy interests of employees and others associated with the company. Protecting corporations from government seizure of their property without just compensation protects all those who have a stake in the corporations鈥 financial well-being. And protecting the free-exercise rights of corporations like Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel protects the religious liberty of the humans who own and control those companies.
In holding that Conestoga, as a 鈥渟ecular, for-profit corporation,鈥 lacks RFRA protection, the Third Circuit wrote as follows:
鈥淕eneral business corporations do not, separate and apart from the actions or belief systems of their individual owners or employees, exercise religion. They do not pray, worship, observe sacraments or take other religiously-motivated actions separate and apart from the intention and direction of their individual actors.鈥 724 F. 3d, at 385 (emphasis added).
All of this is true鈥攂ut quite beside the point. Corporations, 鈥渟eparate and apart from鈥 the human beings who own, run, and are employed by them, cannot do anything at all.
B
1
As we noted above, RFRA applies to 鈥渁 person鈥檚鈥 exercise of religion, 42 U. S. C. 搂搂2000bb鈥1(a), (b), and RFRA itself does not define the term 鈥減erson.鈥 We therefore look to the Dictionary Act, which we must consult 鈥淸i]n determining the meaning of any Act of Congress, unless the context indicates otherwise.鈥 1 U. S. C. 搂1.
Under the Dictionary Act, 鈥渢he wor[d] 鈥榩erson鈥 . . . include[s] corporations, companies, associations, firms, partnerships, societies, and joint stock companies, as well as individuals.鈥 Ibid.; see FCC v. AT&T Inc., 562 U. S. ___, ___ (2011) (slip op., at 6) (鈥淲e have no doubt that 鈥榩erson,鈥 in a legal setting, often refers to artificial entities. The Dictionary Act makes that clear鈥). Thus, unless there is something about the RFRA context that 鈥渋ndicates otherwise,鈥 the Dictionary Act provides a quick, clear, and affirmative answer to the question whether the companies involved in these cases may be heard.
We see nothing in RFRA that suggests a congressional intent to depart from the Dictionary Act definition, and HHS makes little effort to argue otherwise. We have entertained RFRA and free-exercise claims brought by nonprofit corporations, see Gonzales v. O Centro Esp铆rita Beneficiente Uni茫o do Vegetal, 546 U. S. 418 (2006) (RFRA); Hosanna-Tabor Evangelical Lutheran Church and School v. EEOC, 565 U. S. ___ (2012) (Free Exercise); Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. Hialeah, 508 U. S. 520 (1993) (Free Exercise), and HHS concedes that a nonprofit corporation can be a 鈥減erson鈥 within the meaning of RFRA. See Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥354, at 17; Reply Brief in No. 13鈥354, at 7鈥8.[19]
This concession effectively dispatches any argument that the term 鈥減erson鈥 as used in RFRA does not reach the closely held corporations involved in these cases. No known understanding of the term 鈥減erson鈥 includes some but not all corporations. The term 鈥減erson鈥 sometimes encompasses artificial persons (as the Dictionary Act instructs), and it sometimes is limited to natural persons. But no conceivable definition of the term includes natural persons and nonprofit corporations, but not for-profit corporations.[20] Cf. Clark v. Martinez, 543 U. S. 371, 378 (2005) (鈥淭o give th[e] same words a different meaning for each category would be to invent a statute rather than interpret one鈥).
2
The principal argument advanced by HHS and the principal dissent regarding RFRA protection for Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel focuses not on the statutory term 鈥減erson,鈥 but on the phrase 鈥渆xercise of religion.鈥 According to HHS and the dissent, these corporations are not protected by RFRA because they cannot exercise religion. Neither HHS nor the dissent, however, provides any persuasive explanation for this conclusion.
Is it because of the corporate form? The corporate form alone cannot provide the explanation because, as we have pointed out, HHS concedes that nonprofit corporations can be protected by RFRA. The dissent suggests that nonprofit corporations are special because furthering their reli-gious 鈥渁utonomy . . . often furthers individual religious freedom as well.鈥 Post, at 15 (quoting Corporation of Presiding Bishop of Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints v. Amos, 483 U. S. 327, 342 (1987) (Brennan, J., concurring in judgment)). But this principle appliesequally to for-profit corporations: Furthering their re-ligious freedom also 鈥渇urthers individual religious freedom.鈥 In these cases, for example, allowing Hobby Lobby, Con-estoga, and Mardel to assert RFRA claims protects the religious liberty of the Greens and the Hahns.[21]
If the corporate form is not enough, what about the profit-making objective? In Braunfeld, 366 U. S. 599 , we entertained the free-exercise claims of individuals who were attempting to make a profit as retail merchants, and the Court never even hinted that this objective precluded their claims. As the Court explained in a later case, the 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 involves 鈥渘ot only belief and profession but the performance of (or abstention from) physical acts鈥 that are 鈥渆ngaged in for religious reasons.鈥 Smith, 494 U. S., at 877. Business practices that are compelled or limited by the tenets of a religious doctrine fall comfortably within that definition. Thus, a law that 鈥渙perates so as to make the practice of . . . religious beliefs more expensive鈥 in the context of business activities imposes a burden on the exercise of religion. Braunfeld, supra, at 605; see United States v. Lee, 455 U. S. 252, 257 (1982) (recognizing that 鈥渃ompulsory participation in the social security system interferes with [Amish employers鈥橾 free exercise rights鈥).
If, as Braunfeld recognized, a sole proprietorship that seeks to make a profit may assert a free-exercise claim,[22] why can鈥檛 Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel do the same?
Some lower court judges have suggested that RFRA does not protect for-profit corporations because the purpose of such corporations is simply to make money.[23] This argument flies in the face of modern corporate law. 鈥淓ach American jurisdiction today either expressly or by implication authorizes corporations to be formed under its general corporation act for any lawful purpose or business.鈥 1 J. Cox & T. Hazen, Treatise of the Law of Corporations 搂4:1, p. 224 (3d ed. 2010) (emphasis added); see 1A W. Fletcher, Cyclopedia of the Law of Corporations 搂102 (rev. ed. 2010). While it is certainly true that a central objective of for-profit corporations is to make money, modern corporate law does not require for-profit corporations to pursue profit at the expense of everything else, and many do not do so. For-profit corporations, with ownership approval, support a wide variety of charitable causes, and it is not at all uncommon for such corporations to further humanitarian and other altruistic objectives. Many examples come readily to mind. So long as its owners agree, a for-profit corporation may take costly pollution-control and energy-conservation measures that go beyond what the law requires. A for-profit corporation that operates facilities in other countries may exceed the requirements of local law regarding working conditions and benefits. If for-profit corporations may pursue such worthy objectives, there is no apparent reason why they may not further religious objectives as well.
HHS would draw a sharp line between nonprofit corporations (which, HHS concedes, are protected by RFRA) and for-profit corporations (which HHS would leave unprotected), but the actual picture is less clear-cut. Not all corporations that decline to organize as nonprofits do so in order to maximize profit. For example, organizations with religious and charitable aims might organize as for-profit corporations because of the potential advantages of that corporate form, such as the freedom to participate in lobbying for legislation or campaigning for political candidates who promote their religious or charitable goals.[24] In fact, recognizing the inherent compatibility between establishing a for-profit corporation and pursuing nonprofit goals, States have increasingly adopted laws formally recognizing hybrid corporate forms. Over half of the States, for instance, now recognize the 鈥渂enefit corporation,鈥 a dual-purpose entity that seeks to achieve both a benefit for the public and a profit for its owners.[25]
In any event, the objectives that may properly be pursued by the companies in these cases are governed by the laws of the States in which they were incorporated鈥擯ennsylvania and Oklahoma鈥攁nd the laws of those States permit for-profit corporations to pursue 鈥渁ny lawful purpose鈥 or 鈥渁ct,鈥 including the pursuit of profit in conformity with the owners鈥 religious principles. 15 Pa. Cons. Stat. 搂1301 (2001) (鈥淐orporations may be incorporated under this subpart for any lawful purpose or purposes鈥); Okla. Stat., Tit. 18, 搂搂1002, 1005 (West 2012) (鈥淸E]very corporation, whether profit or not for profit鈥 may 鈥渂e incorporated or organized . . . to conduct or promote any lawful business or purposes鈥); see also 搂1006(A)(3); Brief for State of Oklahoma as Amicus Curiae in No. 13鈥354.
3
HHS and the principal dissent make one additional argument in an effort to show that a for-profit corporation cannot engage in the 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 within the meaning of RFRA: HHS argues that RFRA did no more than codify this Court鈥檚 pre-Smith Free Exercise Clause precedents, and because none of those cases squarely held that a for-profit corporation has free-exercise rights, RFRA does not confer such protection. This argument has many flaws.
First, nothing in the text of RFRA as originally enacted suggested that the statutory phrase 鈥渆xercise of religion under the First Amendment鈥 was meant to be tied to this Court鈥檚 pre-Smith interpretation of that Amendment. When first enacted, RFRA defined the 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 to mean 鈥渢he exercise of religion under the First Amendment鈥濃攏ot the exercise of religion as recognized only by then-existing Supreme Court precedents. 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb鈥2(4) (1994 ed.). When Congress wants to link the meaning of a statutory provision to a body of this Court鈥檚 case law, it knows how to do so. See, e.g., Antiterrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act of 1996, 28 U. S. C. 搂2254(d)(1) (authorizing habeas relief from a state-court decision that 鈥渨as contrary to, or involved an unreasonable application of, clearly established Federal law, as determined by the Supreme Court of the United States鈥).
Second, if the original text of RFRA was not clear enough on this point鈥攁nd we think it was鈥攖he amendment of RFRA through RLUIPA surely dispels any doubt. That amendment deleted the prior reference to the First Amendment, see 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb鈥2(4) (2000 ed.) (incorporating 搂2000cc鈥5), and neither HHS nor the principal dissent can explain why Congress did this if it wanted to tie RFRA coverage tightly to the specific holdings of our pre-Smith free-exercise cases. Moreover, as discussed, the amendment went further, providing that the exercise of religion 鈥渟hall be construed in favor of a broad protection of religious exercise, to the maximum extent permitted by the terms of this chapter and the Constitution.鈥 搂2000cc鈥3(g). It is simply not possible to read these provisions as restricting the concept of the 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 to those practices specifically addressed in our pre-Smith decisions.
Third, the one pre-Smith case involving the free-exercise rights of a for-profit corporation suggests, if anything, that for-profit corporations possess such rights. In Gallagher v. Crown Kosher Super Market of Mass., Inc., 366 U. S. 617 (1961) , the Massachusetts Sunday closing law was challenged by a kosher market that was organized as a for-profit corporation, by customers of the market, and by a rabbi. The Commonwealth argued that the corporation lacked 鈥渟tanding鈥 to assert a free-exercise claim,[26] but not one member of the Court expressed agreement with that argument. The plurality opinion for four Justices rejected the First Amendment claim on the merits based on the reasoning in Braunfeld, and reserved decision on the question whether the corporation had 鈥渟tanding鈥 to raise the claim. See 366 U. S., at 631. The three dissenters, Justices Douglas, Brennan, and Stewart, found the law unconstitutional as applied to the corporation and the other challengers and thus implicitly recognized their right to assert a free-exercise claim. See id., at 642 (Brennan, J., joined by Stewart, J., dissenting); McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U. S. 420 鈥579 (1961) (Douglas, J., dissenting as to related cases including Gallagher). Fi-nally, Justice Frankfurter鈥檚 opinion, which was joined by Justice Harlan, upheld the Massachusetts law on the merits but did not question or reserve decision on the issue of the right of the corporation or any of the other challengers to be heard. See McGowan, 366 U. S., at 521鈥522. It is quite a stretch to argue that RFRA, a law enacted to provide very broad protection for religious liberty,left for-profit corporations unprotected simply because in Gallagher鈥攖he only pre-Smith case in which the issue was raised鈥攁 majority of the Justices did not find it necessary to decide whether the kosher market鈥檚 corporate status barred it from raising a free-exercise claim.
Finally, the results would be absurd if RFRA merely restored this Court鈥檚 pre-Smith decisions in ossified form and did not allow a plaintiff to raise a RFRA claim unless that plaintiff fell within a category of plaintiffs one of whom had brought a free-exercise claim that this Court entertained in the years before Smith. For example, we are not aware of any pre-Smith case in which this Court entertained a free-exercise claim brought by a resident noncitizen. Are such persons also beyond RFRA鈥檚 protective reach simply because the Court never addressed their rights before Smith?
Presumably in recognition of the weakness of this argument, both HHS and the principal dissent fall back on the broader contention that the Nation lacks a tradition of exempting for-profit corporations from generally applicable laws. By contrast, HHS contends, statutes like Title VII, 42 U. S. C. 搂2000e鈥19(A), expressly exempt churches and other nonprofit religious institutions but not for-profit corporations. See Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥356, p. 26. In making this argument, however, HHS did not call to our attention the fact that some federal statutes do exempt categories of entities that include for-profit corporations from laws that would otherwise require these entities to engage in activities to which they object on grounds of conscience. See, e.g., 42 U. S. C. 搂300a鈥7(b)(2); 搂238n(a).[27] If Title VII and similar laws show anything, it isthat Congress speaks with specificity when it intends a religious accommodation not to extend to for-profitcorporations.
4
Finally, HHS contends that Congress could not have wanted RFRA to apply to for-profit corporations because it is difficult as a practical matter to ascertain the sincere 鈥渂eliefs鈥 of a corporation. HHS goes so far as to raise the specter of 鈥渄ivisive, polarizing proxy battles over the religious identity of large, publicly traded corporations such as IBM or General Electric.鈥 Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥356, at 30.
These cases, however, do not involve publicly traded corporations, and it seems unlikely that the sort of corporate giants to which HHS refers will often assert RFRA claims. HHS has not pointed to any example of a publicly traded corporation asserting RFRA rights, and numerous practical restraints would likely prevent that from occurring. For example, the idea that unrelated shareholders鈥攊ncluding institutional investors with their own set of stakeholders鈥攚ould agree to run a corporation under the same religious beliefs seems improbable. In any event, we have no occasion in these cases to consider RFRA鈥檚 applicability to such companies. The companies in the cases before us are closely held corporations, each owned and controlled by members of a single family, and no one has disputed the sincerity of their religious beliefs.[28]
HHS has also provided no evidence that the purported problem of determining the sincerity of an asserted religious belief moved Congress to exclude for-profit corporations from RFRA鈥檚 protection. On the contrary, the scope of RLUIPA shows that Congress was confident of the ability of the federal courts to weed out insincere claims. RLUIPA applies to 鈥渋nstitutionalized persons,鈥 a category that consists primarily of prisoners, and by the time of RLUIPA鈥檚 enactment, the propensity of some prisoners to assert claims of dubious sincerity was well documented.[29] Nevertheless, after our decision in City of Boerne, Congress enacted RLUIPA to preserve the right of prisoners to raise religious liberty claims. If Congress thought that the federal courts were up to the job of dealing with insincere prisoner claims, there is no reason to believe that Congress limited RFRA鈥檚 reach out of concern for the seem-ingly less difficult task of doing the same in corporate cases. And if, as HHS seems to concede, Congress wanted RFRA to apply to nonprofit corporations, see, Reply Brief in No. 13鈥354, at 7鈥8, what reason is there to think that Congress believed that spotting insincere claims wouldbe tougher in cases involving for-profits?
HHS and the principal dissent express concern about the possibility of disputes among the owners of corporations, but that is not a problem that arises because of RFRA or that is unique to this context. The owners of closely held corporations may鈥攁nd sometimes do鈥攄isagree about the conduct of business. 1 Treatise of the Law of Corporations 搂14:11. And even if RFRA did not exist, the owners of a company might well have a dispute relating to religion. For example, some might want a company鈥檚 stores to remain open on the Sabbath in order to make more money, and others might want the stores to close for religious reasons. State corporate law provides a ready means for resolving any conflicts by, for example, dictating how a corporation can establish its governing structure. See, e.g., ibid; id., 搂3:2; Del. Code Ann., Tit. 8, 搂351 (2011) (providing that certificate of incorporation may provide how 鈥渢he business of the corporation shall be managed鈥). Courts will turn to that structure and the underlying state law in resolving disputes.
For all these reasons, we hold that a federal regulation鈥檚 restriction on the activities of a for-profit closely held corporation must comply with RFRA.[30]
IV
Because RFRA applies in these cases, we must next ask whether the HHS contraceptive mandate 鈥渟ubstantially burden[s]鈥 the exercise of religion. 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb鈥1(a). We have little trouble concluding that it does.
A
As we have noted, the Hahns and Greens have a sincere religious belief that life begins at conception. They therefore object on religious grounds to providing health insurance that covers methods of birth control that, as HHS acknowledges, see Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥354, at 9, n. 4, may result in the destruction of an embryo. By requiring the Hahns and Greens and their companies to arrange for such coverage, the HHS mandate demands that they engage in conduct that seriously violates their religious beliefs.
If the Hahns and Greens and their companies do not yield to this demand, the economic consequences will be severe. If the companies continue to offer group health plans that do not cover the contraceptives at issue, they will be taxed $100 per day for each affected individual. 26 U. S. C. 搂4980D. For Hobby Lobby, the bill could amount to $1.3 million per day or about $475 million per year; for Conestoga, the assessment could be $90,000 per day or $33 million per year; and for Mardel, it could be $40,000 per day or about $15 million per year. These sums are surely substantial.
It is true that the plaintiffs could avoid these assessments by dropping insurance coverage altogether and thus forcing their employees to obtain health insurance on one of the exchanges established under ACA. But if at least one of their full-time employees were to qualify for a subsidy on one of the government-run exchanges, this course would also entail substantial economic consequences. The companies could face penalties of $2,000 per employee each year. 搂4980H. These penalties would amount to roughly $26 million for Hobby Lobby, $1.8 million for Conestoga, and $800,000 for Mardel.
B
Although these totals are high, amici supporting HHS have suggested that the $2,000 per-employee penalty is actually less than the average cost of providing health insurance, see Brief for Religious Organizations 22, and therefore, they claim, the companies could readily eliminate any substantial burden by forcing their employees to obtain insurance in the government exchanges. We do not generally entertain arguments that were not raised below and are not advanced in this Court by any party, see United Parcel Service, Inc. v. Mitchell, 451 U. S. 56 , n. 2 (1981); Bell v. Wolfish, 441 U. S. 520 , n. 13 (1979); Knetsch v. United States, 364 U. S. 361, 370 (1960) , and there are strong reasons to adhere to that practice in these cases. HHS, which presumably could have compiled the relevant statistics, has never made this argument鈥攏ot in its voluminous briefing or at oral argument in this Court nor, to our knowledge, in any of the numerous cases in which the issue now before us has been litigated around the country. As things now stand, we do not even know what the Government鈥檚 position might be with respect to these amici鈥檚 intensely empirical argument.[31] For this same reason, the plaintiffs have never had an opportunity to respond to this novel claim that鈥攃ontrary to their longstanding practice and that of most large employers鈥攖hey would be better off discarding their employer insurance plans altogether.
Even if we were to reach this argument, we would find it unpersuasive. As an initial matter, it entirely ignores the fact that the Hahns and Greens and their companies have religious reasons for providing health-insurance coverage for their employees. Before the advent of ACA, they were not legally compelled to provide insurance, but they nevertheless did so鈥攊n part, no doubt, for conventional business reasons, but also in part because their religious beliefs govern their relations with their employees. See App. to Pet. for Cert. in No. 13鈥356, p. 11g; App. in No. 13鈥354, at 139.
Putting aside the religious dimension of the decision to provide insurance, moreover, it is far from clear that the net cost to the companies of providing insurance is more than the cost of dropping their insurance plans and paying the ACA penalty. Health insurance is a benefit that employees value. If the companies simply eliminated that benefit and forced employees to purchase their own insurance on the exchanges, without offering additional compensation, it is predictable that the companies would face a competitive disadvantage in retaining and attracting skilled workers. See App. in No. 13鈥354, at 153.
The companies could attempt to make up for the elimination of a group health plan by increasing wages, but this would be costly. Group health insurance is generally less expensive than comparable individual coverage, so the amount of the salary increase needed to fully compensate for the termination of insurance coverage may well exceed the cost to the companies of providing the insurance. In addition, any salary increase would have to take into account the fact that employees must pay income taxes on wages but not on the value of employer-provided health insurance. 26 U. S. C. 搂106(a). Likewise, employers can deduct the cost of providing health insurance, see 搂162(a)(1), but apparently cannot deduct the amount of the penalty that they must pay if insurance is not pro-vided; that difference also must be taken into account. Given these economic incentives, it is far from clear that it would be financially advantageous for an employer to drop coverage and pay the penalty.[32]
In sum, we refuse to sustain the challenged regulations on the ground鈥攏ever maintained by the Government鈥攖hat dropping insurance coverage eliminates the substantial burden that the HHS mandate imposes. We doubt that the Congress that enacted RFRA鈥攐r, for that matter, ACA鈥攚ould have believed it a tolerable result to put family-run businesses to the choice of violating their sincerely held religious beliefs or making all of their employees lose their existing healthcare plans.
C
In taking the position that the HHS mandate does not impose a substantial burden on the exercise of religion, HHS鈥檚 main argument (echoed by the principal dissent) is basically that the connection between what the objecting parties must do (provide health-insurance coverage for four methods of contraception that may operate after the fertilization of an egg) and the end that they find to be morally wrong (destruction of an embryo) is simply too attenuated. Brief for HHS in 13鈥354, pp. 31鈥34; post, at 22鈥23. HHS and the dissent note that providing the coverage would not itself result in the destruction of an embryo; that would occur only if an employee chose to take advantage of the coverage and to use one of the four methods at issue.[33] Ibid.
This argument dodges the question that RFRA presents (whether the HHS mandate imposes a substantial burden on the ability of the objecting parties to conduct business in accordance with their religious beliefs) and instead addresses a very different question that the federal courts have no business addressing (whether the religious belief asserted in a RFRA case is reasonable). The Hahns and Greens believe that providing the coverage demanded by the HHS regulations is connected to the destruction of an embryo in a way that is sufficient to make it immoral for them to provide the coverage. This belief implicates a difficult and important question of religion and moral philosophy, namely, the circumstances under which it is wrong for a person to perform an act that is innocent in itself but that has the effect of enabling or facilitating the commission of an immoral act by another.[34] Arrogating the authority to provide a binding national answer to this religious and philosophical question, HHS and the principal dissent in effect tell the plaintiffs that their beliefs are flawed. For good reason, we have repeatedly refused to take such a step. See, e.g., Smith, 494 U. S., at 887 (鈥淩epeatedly and in many different contexts, we have warned that courts must not presume to determine . . . the plausibility of a religious claim鈥); Hernandez v. Commissioner, 490 U. S. 680, 699 (1989) ; Presbyterian Church in U. S. v. Mary Elizabeth Blue Hull Memorial Presbyterian Church, 393 U. S. 440, 450 (1969) .
Moreover, in Thomas v. Review Bd. of Indiana Employment Security Div., 450 U. S. 707 (1981) , we considered and rejected an argument that is nearly identical to the one now urged by HHS and the dissent. In Thomas, a Jehovah鈥檚 Witness was initially employed making sheet steel for a variety of industrial uses, but he was later transferred to a job making turrets for tanks. Id., at 710. Because he objected on religious grounds to participating in the manufacture of weapons, he lost his job and sought unemployment compensation. Ruling against the em-ployee, the state court had difficulty with the line thatthe employee drew between work that he found to be con-sistent with his religious beliefs (helping to manufacture steel that was used in making weapons) and work that he found morally objectionable (helping to make the weapons themselves). This Court, however, held that 鈥渋t is not for us to say that the line he drew was an unreasonable one.鈥 Id., at 715.[35]
Similarly, in these cases, the Hahns and Greens and their companies sincerely believe that providing the insurance coverage demanded by the HHS regulations lies on the forbidden side of the line, and it is not for us to say that their religious beliefs are mistaken or insubstantial. Instead, our 鈥渘arrow function . . . in this context is to determine鈥 whether the line drawn reflects 鈥渁n honest conviction,鈥 id., at 716, and there is no dispute that it does.
HHS nevertheless compares these cases to decisions in which we rejected the argument that the use of general tax revenue to subsidize the secular activities of religious institutions violated the Free Exercise Clause. See Tilton v. Richardson, 403 U. S. 672, 689 (1971) (plurality); Board of Ed. of Central School Dist. No. 1 v. Allen, 392 U. S. 236 鈥249 (1968). But in those cases, while the subsidies were clearly contrary to the challengers鈥 views on a secular issue, namely, proper church-state relations, the challengers never articulated a religious objection to the subsidies. As we put it in Tilton, they were 鈥渦nable to identify any coercion directed at the practice or exercise of their religious beliefs.鈥 403 U. S., at 689 (plurality opinion); see Allen, supra, at 249 (鈥淸A]ppellants have not contended that the New York law in any way coerces them as individuals in the practice of their religion鈥). Here, in contrast, the plaintiffs do assert that funding the specific contraceptive methods at issue violates their religious beliefs, and HHS does not question their sincerity. Because the contraceptive mandate forces them to pay an enormous sum of money鈥攁s much as $475 million per year in the case of Hobby Lobby鈥攊f they insist on providing insurance coverage in accordance with their religious beliefs, the mandate clearly imposes a substantial burden on those beliefs.
V
Since the HHS contraceptive mandate imposes a substantial burden on the exercise of religion, we must move on and decide whether HHS has shown that the mandate both 鈥(1) is in furtherance of a compelling governmental interest; and (2) is the least restrictive means of furthering that compelling governmental interest.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb鈥1(b).
A
HHS asserts that the contraceptive mandate serves a variety of important interests, but many of these are couched in very broad terms, such as promoting 鈥減ublic health鈥 and 鈥済ender equality.鈥 Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥354, at 46, 49. RFRA, however, contemplates a 鈥渕ore focused鈥 inquiry: It 鈥渞equires the Government to demonstrate that the compelling interest test is satisfied through application of the challenged law 鈥榯o the person鈥欌攖he particular claimant whose sincere exercise of religion is being substantially burdened.鈥 O鈥機entro, 546 U. S., at 430鈥431 (quoting 搂2000bb鈥1(b)). This requires us to 鈥渓oo[k] beyond broadly formulated interests鈥 and to 鈥渟crutiniz[e] the asserted harm of granting specific exemptions to particular religious claimants鈥濃攊n other words, to look to the marginal interest in enforcing the contraceptive mandate in these cases. O Centro, supra, at 431.
In addition to asserting these very broadly framed interests, HHS maintains that the mandate serves a compelling interest in ensuring that all women have access to all FDA-approved contraceptives without cost sharing. See Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥354, at 14鈥15, 49; see Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥356, at 10, 48. Under our cases, women (and men) have a constitutional right to obtain contraceptives, see Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 鈥486 (1965), and HHS tells us that 鈥淸s]tudies have demonstrated that even moderate copayments for preventive services can deter patients from receiving those services.鈥 Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥354, at 50 (internal quotation marks omitted).
The objecting parties contend that HHS has not shown that the mandate serves a compelling government interest, and it is arguable that there are features of ACA that support that view. As we have noted, many employees鈥攖hose covered by grandfathered plans and those who work for employers with fewer than 50 employees鈥攎ay have no contraceptive coverage without cost sharing at all.
HHS responds that many legal requirements have exceptions and the existence of exceptions does not in itself indicate that the principal interest served by a law is not compelling. Even a compelling interest may be outweighed in some circumstances by another even weightier consideration. In these cases, however, the interest served by one of the biggest exceptions, the exception for grandfathered plans, is simply the interest of employers in avoiding the inconvenience of amending an existing plan. Grandfathered plans are required 鈥渢o comply with a subset of the Affordable Care Act鈥檚 health reform provisions鈥 that provide what HHS has described as 鈥減articularly significant protections.鈥 75 Fed. Reg. 34540 (2010). But the contraceptive mandate is expressly excluded from this subset. Ibid.
We find it unnecessary to adjudicate this issue. We will assume that the interest in guaranteeing cost-free access to the four challenged contraceptive methods is compelling within the meaning of RFRA, and we will proceed to consider the final prong of the RFRA test, i.e., whether HHS has shown that the contraceptive mandate is 鈥渢he least restrictive means of furthering that compelling governmental interest.鈥 搂2000bb鈥1(b)(2).
B
The least-restrictive-means standard is exceptionally demanding, see City of Boerne, 521 U. S., at 532, and it is not satisfied here. HHS has not shown that it lacks other means of achieving its desired goal without imposing a substantial burden on the exercise of religion by the objecting parties in these cases. See 搂搂2000bb鈥1(a), (b) (requiring the Government to 鈥渄emonstrat[e] that application of [a substantial] burden to the person . . . is the least restrictive means of furthering [a] compelling governmental interest鈥 (emphasis added)).
The most straightforward way of doing this would be for the Government to assume the cost of providing the four contraceptives at issue to any women who are unable to obtain them under their health-insurance policies due to their employers鈥 religious objections. This would certainly be less restrictive of the plaintiffs鈥 religious liberty, and HHS has not shown, see 搂2000bb鈥1(b)(2), that this is not a viable alternative. HHS has not provided any estimate of the average cost per employee of providing access tothese contraceptives, two of which, according to the FDA, are designed primarily for emergency use. See Birth Control: Medicines to Help You, online at http://www.fda.gov/forconsumers/byaudience/forwomen/freepublications/ucm313215.htm. Nor has HHS provided any statistics regarding the number of employees who might be affected because they work for corporations like Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel. Nor has HHS told us that it is unable to provide such statistics. It seems likely, however, that the cost of providing the forms of contraceptives at issue in these cases (if not all FDA-approved contraceptives) would be minor when compared with the overall cost of ACA. According to one of the Congressional Budget Office鈥檚 most recent forecasts, ACA鈥檚 insurance-coverage provisions will cost the Federal Government more than $1.3 trillion through the next decade. See CBO, Updated Estimates of the Effects of the Insurance Coverage Provisions of the Affordable Care Act, April 2014, p. 2.[36] If, as HHS tells us, providing all women with cost-free access to all FDA-approved methods of contraception is a Government interest of the highest order, it is hard to understand HHS鈥檚 argument that it cannot be required under RFRA to pay anything in order to achieve this important goal.
HHS contends that RFRA does not permit us to take this option into account because 鈥淩FRA cannot be used to require creation of entirely new programs.鈥 Brief for HHS in 13鈥354, at 15.[37] But we see nothing in RFRA that supports this argument, and drawing the line between the 鈥渃reation of an entirely new program鈥 and the modification of an existing program (which RFRA surely allows) would be fraught with problems. We do not doubt that cost may be an important factor in the least-restrictive-means analysis, but both RFRA and its sister statute, RLUIPA, may in some circumstances require the Government to expend additional funds to accommodate citizens鈥 religious beliefs. Cf. 搂2000cc鈥3(c) (RLUIPA: 鈥淸T]his chapter may require a government to incur expenses in its own operations to avoid imposing a substantial burden on religious exercise.鈥). HHS鈥檚 view that RFRA can never require the Government to spend even a small amount reflects a judgment about the importance of religious liberty that was not shared by the Congress that enacted that law.
In the end, however, we need not rely on the option of a new, government-funded program in order to conclude that the HHS regulations fail the least-restrictive-means test. HHS itself has demonstrated that it has at its disposal an approach that is less restrictive than requiring employers to fund contraceptive methods that violate their religious beliefs. As we explained above, HHS has already established an accommodation for nonprofit organizations with religious objections. See supra, at 9鈥10, and nn. 8鈥9. Under that accommodation, the organization can self-certify that it opposes providing coverage for particular contraceptive services. See 45 CFR 搂搂147.131(b)(4), (c)(1); 26 CFR 搂搂54.9815鈥2713A(a)(4), (b). If the organization makes such a certification, the organization鈥檚 insurance issuer or third-party administrator must 鈥淸e]xpressly exclude contraceptive coverage from the group health insurance coverage provided in connection with the group health plan鈥 and 鈥淸p]rovide separate payments for any contraceptive services required to be covered鈥 without imposing 鈥渁ny cost-sharing requirements . . . on the eligible organization, the group health plan, or plan participants or beneficiaries.鈥 45 CFR 搂147.131(c)(2); 26 CFR 搂54.9815鈥2713A(c)(2).[38]
We do not decide today whether an approach of this type complies with RFRA for purposes of all religious claims.[39] At a minimum, however, it does not impinge on the plaintiffs鈥 religious belief that providing insurance coverage for the contraceptives at issue here violates their religion, and it serves HHS鈥檚 stated interests equally well.[40]
The principal dissent identifies no reason why this accommodation would fail to protect the asserted needs of women as effectively as the contraceptive mandate, and there is none.[41] Under the accommodation, the plaintiffs鈥 female employees would continue to receive contraceptive coverage without cost sharing for all FDA-approved contraceptives, and they would continue to 鈥渇ace minimal logistical and administrative obstacles,鈥 post, at 28 (internal quotation marks omitted), because their employers鈥 insurers would be responsible for providing information and coverage, see, e.g., 45 CFR 搂搂147.131(c)鈥(d); cf. 26 CFR 搂搂54.9815鈥2713A(b), (d). Ironically, it is the dissent鈥檚 approach that would 鈥淸i]mped[e] women鈥檚 receipt of benefits by 鈥榬equiring them to take steps to learn about, and to sign up for, a new government funded and administered health benefit,鈥 鈥 post, at 28, because the dissent would effectively compel religious employers to drop health-insurance coverage altogether, leaving their employees to find individual plans on government-run exchanges or elsewhere. This is indeed 鈥渟carcely what Congress contemplated.鈥 Ibid.
C
HHS and the principal dissent argue that a ruling in favor of the objecting parties in these cases will lead to a flood of religious objections regarding a wide variety of medical procedures and drugs, such as vaccinations and blood transfusions, but HHS has made no effort to substantiate this prediction.[42] HHS points to no evidence that insurance plans in existence prior to the enactment of ACA excluded coverage for such items. Nor has HHS provided evidence that any significant number of employers sought exemption, on religious grounds, from any of ACA鈥檚 coverage requirements other than the contraceptive mandate.
It is HHS鈥檚 apparent belief that no insurance-coverage mandate would violate RFRA鈥攏o matter how significantly it impinges on the religious liberties of employers鈥攖hat would lead to intolerable consequences. Under HHS鈥檚 view, RFRA would permit the Government to require all employers to provide coverage for any medical procedure allowed by law in the jurisdiction in question鈥攆or instance, third-trimester abortions or assisted suicide. The owners of many closely held corporations could not in good conscience provide such coverage, and thus HHS would effectively exclude these people from full participation in the economic life of the Nation. RFRA was enacted to prevent such an outcome.
In any event, our decision in these cases is concerned solely with the contraceptive mandate. Our decision should not be understood to hold that an insurance-coverage mandate must necessarily fall if it conflicts with an employer鈥檚 religious beliefs. Other coverage requirements, such as immunizations, may be supported by different interests (for example, the need to combat the spread of infectious diseases) and may involve different arguments about the least restrictive means of providing them.
The principal dissent raises the possibility that discrimination in hiring, for example on the basis of race, might be cloaked as religious practice to escape legal sanction. See post, at 32鈥33. Our decision today provides no such shield. The Government has a compelling interest in providing an equal opportunity to participate in the workforce without regard to race, and prohibitions on racial discrimination are precisely tailored to achieve that critical goal.
HHS also raises for the first time in this Court the argument that applying the contraceptive mandate to for-profit employers with sincere religious objections is essential to the comprehensive health-insurance scheme that ACA establishes. HHS analogizes the contraceptive mandate to the requirement to pay Social Security taxes, which we upheld in Lee despite the religious objection of an employer, but these cases are quite different. Our holding in Lee turned primarily on the special problems associated with a national system of taxation. We noted that 鈥淸t]he obligation to pay the social security tax initially is not fundamentally different from the obligation to pay income taxes.鈥 455 U. S., at 260. Based on that premise, we explained that it was untenable to allow individuals to seek exemptions from taxes based on religious objections to particular Government expenditures: 鈥淚f, for example, a religious adherent believes war is a sin, and if a certain percentage of the federal budget can be identified as devoted to war-related activities, such individuals would have a similarly valid claim to be exempt from paying that percentage of the income tax.鈥 Ibid. We observed that 鈥淸t]he tax system could not function if denominations were allowed to challenge the tax system because tax payments were spent in a manner that violates their religious belief.鈥 Ibid.; see O Centro, 546 U. S., at 435.
Lee was a free-exercise, not a RFRA, case, but if the issue in Lee were analyzed under the RFRA framework, the fundamental point would be that there simply is no less restrictive alternative to the categorical requirement to pay taxes. Because of the enormous variety of government expenditures funded by tax dollars, allowing tax-payers to withhold a portion of their tax obligations on religious grounds would lead to chaos. Recognizingexemptions from the contraceptive mandate is very different. ACA does not create a large national pool of tax revenue for use in purchasing healthcare coverage. Rather, individual employers like the plaintiffs purchase insurance for their own employees. And contrary to the principal dissent鈥檚 characterization, the employers鈥 contributions do not necessarily funnel into 鈥渦ndifferentiated funds.鈥 Post, at 23. The accommodation established by HHS requires issuers to have a mechanism by which to 鈥渟egregate premium revenue collected from the eligible organization from the monies used to provide payments for contraceptive services.鈥 45 CFR 搂147.131(c)(2)(ii). Recognizing a religious accommodation under RFRA for particular coverage requirements, therefore, does not threaten the viability of ACA鈥檚 comprehensive scheme in the way that recognizing religious objections to particular expenditures from general tax revenues would.[43]
In its final pages, the principal dissent reveals that its fundamental objection to the claims of the plaintiffs is an objection to RFRA itself. The dissent worries about forcing the federal courts to apply RFRA to a host of claims made by litigants seeking a religious exemption from generally applicable laws, and the dissent expresses a desire to keep the courts out of this business. See post, at 32鈥35. In making this plea, the dissent reiterates a point made forcefully by the Court in Smith. 494 U. S., at 888鈥889 (applying the Sherbert test to all free-exercise claims 鈥渨ould open the prospect of constitutionally required religious exemptions from civic obligations of almost every conceivable kind鈥). But Congress, in enacting RFRA, took the position that 鈥渢he compelling interest test as set forth in prior Federal court rulings is a workable test forstriking sensible balances between religious liberty and competing prior governmental interests.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb(a)(5). The wisdom of Congress鈥檚 judgment on this matter is not our concern. Our responsibility is to enforce RFRA as written, and under the standard that RFRA prescribes, the HHS contraceptive mandate is unlawful.
*鈥冣赌*鈥冣赌*
The contraceptive mandate, as applied to closely held corporations, violates RFRA. Our decision on that statutory question makes it unnecessary to reach the First Amendment claim raised by Conestoga and the Hahns.
The judgment of the Tenth Circuit in No. 13鈥354 is affirmed; the judgment of the Third Circuit in No. 13鈥356 is reversed, and that case is remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered.
Notes
[1] See also , at 8 (鈥淭he exemption sought by Hobby Lobby and Conestoga . . . would deny [their employees] access to contraceptive coverage that the ACA would otherwise secure鈥)
[2] The Act defines 鈥済overnment鈥 to include any 鈥渄epartment鈥 or鈥渁gency鈥 of the United States. 搂2000bb鈥2(1).
[3] In v. , 521 U. S., 507 (1997), we wrote that RFRA鈥檚 鈥渓east restrictive means requirement was not used in the pre-jurisprudence RFRA purported to codify.鈥 , at 509. On this understanding of our pre- cases, RFRA did more than merely restore the balancing test used in the line of cases; it provided even broader protection for religious liberty than was available under those decisions.
[4] See, , v., 441 F. 3d 96, 108 (CA2 2006); v., 290 F. 3d 1210, 1220 (CA9 2002).
[5] The principal dissent appears to contend that this rule of construction should apply only when defining the 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 in an RLUIPA case, but not in a RFRA case. See , at 11, n. 10. That argument is plainly wrong. Under this rule of construction, the phrase 鈥渆xercise of religion,鈥 as it appears in RLUIPA, must be interpreted broadly, and RFRA states that the same phrase, as used in RFRA, means 鈥渞eligious exercis[e] as defined in [RLUIPA].鈥 鈥2(4). It necessarily follows that the 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 under RFRA must be given the same broad meaning that applies under RLUIPA.
[6] We will use 鈥淏rief for HHS鈥 to refer to the Brief for Petitioners in No. 13鈥354 and the Brief for Respondents in No. 13鈥356. The federal parties are the Departments of HHS, Treasury, and Labor, and the Secretaries of those Departments.
[7] Online at http://www.fda.gov/forconsumers/byaudience/forwomen/freepublications/ucm313215.htm. The owners of the companies involved in these cases and others who believe that life begins at conception regard these four methods as causing abortions, but federal regulations, which define pregnancy as beginning at implantation, see, ., 62 Fed. Reg. 8611 (1997); 45 CFR 搂46.202(f) (2013), do not so classify them.
[8] In the case of self-insured religious organizations entitled to the accommodation, the third-party administrator of the organization must 鈥減rovide or arrange payments for contraceptive services鈥 for the organization鈥檚 employees without imposing any cost-sharing requirements on the eligible organization, its insurance plan, or its employee beneficiaries. 78 Fed. Reg. 39893 (to be codified in 26 CFR 搂54.9815鈥2713A(b)(2)). The regulations establish a mechanism for these third-party administrators to be compensated for their expenses by obtaining a reduction in the fee paid by insurers to participate in the federally facilitated exchanges. See 78 Fed. Reg. 39893 (to be codified in 26 CFR 搂54.9815鈥2713A (b)(3)). HHS believes that these fee reductions will not materially affect funding of the exchanges because 鈥減ayments for contraceptive services will represent only a small portion of total [exchange] user fees.鈥 78 Fed. Reg. 39882.
[9] In a separate challenge to this framework for religious nonprofit organizations, the Court recently ordered that, pending appeal, the eligible organizations be permitted to opt out of the contraceptive mandate by providing written notification of their objections to the Secretary of HHS, rather than to their insurance issuers or third-party administrators. See v. , 571 U. S. ___ (2014).
[10] While the Government predicts that this number will decline over time, the total number of Americans working for employers to whom the contraceptive mandate does not apply is still substantial, and there is no legal requirement that grandfathered plans ever be phased out.
[11] Online at http : / / www . whitehouse . gov / files / documents / health _reform_for_small_businesses.pdf.
[12] Mennonite Church USA, Statement on Abortion, online athttp://www.mennoniteusa.org /resource-center/resources /statements -and-resolutions/statement-on-abortion/.
[13] The Hahns and Conestoga also claimed that the contraceptive mandate violates the and the Administrative Procedure Act, , but those claims are not before us.
[14] See, , WebMD Health News, New Morning-After Pill Ella Wins FDA Approval, online at http://www.webmd.com/sex/birth-control/news/20100813/new-morning-after-pill-ella-wins-fda-approval.
[15] The Greens operate Hobby Lobby and Mardel through a management trust, of which each member of the family serves as trustee. 723 F. 3d 1114, 1122 (CA10 2013). The family provided that the trust would also be governed according to their religious principles.
[16] They also raised a claim under the Administrative Procedure Act, .
[17] Given its RFRA ruling, the court declined to address the plaintiffs鈥 free-exercise claim or the question whether the Greens could bring RFRA claims as individual owners of Hobby Lobby and Mardel. Four judges, however, concluded that the Greens could do so, see 723 F. 3d, at 1156 (Gorsuch, J., concurring); , at 1184 (Matheson, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part), and three of those judges would have granted plaintiffs a preliminary injunction, see , at 1156 (Gorsuch, J., concurring).
[18] As discussed, n. 3, , in we stated that RFRA, by imposing a least-restrictive-means test, went beyond what was required by our pre-decisions. Although the author of the principal dissent joined the Court鈥檚 opinion in , she now claims that the statement was incorrect. , at 12. For present purposes, it is unnecessary to adjudicate this dispute. Even if RFRA simply restored the status quo ante, there is no reason to believe, as HHS and the dissent seem to suggest, that the law was meant to be limited to situations that fall squarely within the holdings of pre- cases. See , at 25鈥28.
[19] Cf. Brief for Federal Petitioners in , O. T. 2004, No. 04鈥1084, p. II (stating that the organizational respondent was 鈥渁 New Mexico Corporation鈥); Brief for Federal Respondent in , O. T. 2011, No. 10鈥553, p. 3 (stating that the petitioner was an 鈥渆cclesiastical corporation鈥).
[20] Not only does the Government concede that the term 鈥減ersons鈥 in RFRA includes nonprofit corporations, it goes further and appears to concede that the term might also encompass other artificial entities, namely, general partnerships and unincorporated associations. See Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥354, at 28, 40.
[21] Although the principal dissent seems to think that Justice Brennan鈥檚 statement in provides a ground for holding that for-profit corporations may not assert free-exercise claims, that was not Justice Brennan鈥檚 view. See v., (dissenting opinion); , at 26鈥27.
[22] It is revealing that the principal dissent cannot even bring itself to acknowledge that was correct in entertaining the merchants鈥 claims. See at 19 (dismissing the relevance of in part because 鈥淸t]he free exercise claim asserted there was promptly rejected on the merits鈥).
[23] See, ., 724 F. 3d, at 385 (鈥淲e do not see how a for-profit, 鈥榓rtificial being,鈥 . . . that was created to make money鈥 could exercise religion); v., 708 F. 3d 850, 857 (CA7 2013) (Rovner, J. dissenting) (鈥淪o far as it appears, the mission of Grote Industries, like that of any other for-profit, secular business, is to make money in the commercial sphere鈥); v., 730 F. 3d 618, 626 (CA7 2013) (鈥淐ongress did not intend to include corporations primarily organized for secular, profit-seeking purposes as 鈥榩ersons鈥 under RFRA鈥); see also 723 F. 3d, at 1171鈥1172 (Briscoe, C. J., dissenting) (鈥淸T]he specific purpose for which [a corporation] is created matters greatly to how it will be categorized and treated under the law鈥 and 鈥渋t is undisputed that Hobby Lobby and Mardel are for-profit corporations focused on selling merchandise to consumers鈥).
[24] See, , M. Sanders, Joint Ventures Involving Tax-Exempt Organizations 555 (4th ed. 2013) (describing Google.org, which 鈥渁dvance[s] its charitable goals鈥 while operating as a for-profit corporation to be able to 鈥渋nvest in for-profit endeavors, lobby for policies that support its philanthropic goals, and tap Google鈥檚 innovative technology and workforce鈥 (internal quotation marks and alterations omitted)); cf. 26 CFR 搂1.501(c)(3)鈥1(c)(3).
[25] See Benefit Corp Information Center, online at http://www.benefitcorp.net/state-by-state-legislative-status; , Va. Code Ann. 搂搂13.1鈥787, 13.1鈥626, 13.1鈥782 (Lexis 2011) (鈥淎 benefit corporation shall have as one of its purposes the purpose of creating a general public benefit,鈥 and 鈥渕ay identify one or more specific public benefits that it is the purpose of the benefit corporation to create. . . . This purpose is in addition to [the purpose of engaging in any lawful business].鈥 鈥 鈥楽pecific public benefit鈥 means a benefit that serves one or more public welfare, religious, charitable, scientific, literary, or educational purposes, or other purpose or benefit beyond the strict interest of the shareholders of the benefit corporation . . . .鈥); S. C. Code Ann. 搂搂33鈥38鈥300 (2012 Cum. Supp.), 33鈥3鈥101 (2006), 33鈥38鈥130 (2012 Cum. Supp.) (similar).
[26] See Brief for Appellants in , O. T. 1960 No. 11, pp. 16, 28鈥31 (arguing that corporation 鈥渉as no 鈥榬eligious belief鈥 or 鈥榬eligious liberty,鈥 and had no standing in court to assert that its free exercise of religion was impaired鈥).
[27] The principal dissent points out that 鈥渢he exemption codified in 搂238n(a) was not enacted until three years after RFRA鈥檚 passage.鈥 , at 16, n. 15. The dissent takes this to mean that RFRA did not, in fact, 鈥渙pe[n] all statutory schemes to religion-based challenges by for-profit corporations鈥 because if it had 鈥渢here would be no need for a statute-specific, post-RFRA exemption of this sort.鈥 .
[28] To qualify for RFRA鈥檚 protection, an asserted belief must be 鈥渟incere鈥; a corporation鈥檚 pretextual assertion of a religious belief in order to obtain an exemption for financial reasons would fail. Cf., ., v. , 608 F. 3d 717, 718鈥719 (CA10 2010).
[29] See, , v. , 90 F. 3d 293, 296 (CA8 1996); v., 525 F. Supp. 81, 83鈥84 (ED Mo. 1981);v. , 1996 WL 5320, *5 (CA9, Jan. 5, 1996);v., 549 N. W. 2d 819鈥820 (Iowa 1996).
[30] The principal dissent attaches significance to the fact that the 鈥淪enate voted down [a] so-called 鈥榗onscience amendment,鈥 which would have enabled any employer or insurance provider to deny coverage based on its asserted religious beliefs or moral convictions.鈥 , at 6. The dissent would evidently glean from that vote an intent by the Senate to prohibit for-profit corporate employers from refusing to offer contraceptive coverage for religious reasons, regardless of whether the contraceptive mandate could pass muster under RFRA鈥檚 standards. But that is not the only plausible inference from the failed amendment鈥攐r even the most likely. For one thing, the text of the amendment was 鈥渨ritten so broadly that it would allow any employer to deny any health service to any American for virtually any reason鈥.鈥 158 Cong. Rec. S1165 (Mar. 1, 2012) (emphasis added). Moreover, the amendment would have authorized a blanket exemption for religious or moral objectors; it would not have subjected religious-based objections to the judicial scrutiny called for by RFRA, in which a court must consider not only the burden of a requirement on religious adherents, but also the government鈥檚 interest and how narrowly tailored the requirement is. It is thus perfectly reasonable to believe that the amendment was voted down because it extended more broadly than the pre-existing protections of RFRA. And in any event, even if a rejected amendment to a bill could be relevant in other contexts, it surely cannot be relevant here, because any 鈥淔ederal statutory law adopted after November 16, 1993 is subject to [RFRA] unless such law such application by reference to [RFRA].鈥 鈥3(b) (emphasis added). It is not plausible to find such an explicit reference in the meager legislative history on which the dissent relies.
[31] Indeed, one of HHS鈥檚 stated reasons for establishing the religious accommodation was to 鈥渆ncourag[e] eligible organizations to to offer health coverage.鈥 78 Fed. Reg. 39882 (2013) (emphasis added).
[32] Attempting to compensate for dropped insurance by raising wages would also present administrative difficulties. In order to provide full compensation for employees, the companies would have to calculate the value to employees of the convenience of retaining their employer-provided coverage and thus being spared the task of attempting to find and sign up for a comparable plan on an exchange. And because some but not all of the companies鈥 employees may qualify for subsidies on an exchange, it would be nearly impossible to calculate a salary increase that would accurately restore the status quo ante for all employees.
[33] This argument is not easy to square with the position taken by HHS in providing exemptions from the contraceptive mandate for religious employers, such as churches, that have the very same religious objections as the Hahns and Greens and their companies. The connection between what these religious employers would be required to do if not exempted (provide insurance coverage for particular contraceptives) and the ultimate event that they find morally wrong (destruction of an embryo) is exactly the same. Nevertheless, as discussed, HHS and the Labor and Treasury Departments authorized the exemption from the contraceptive mandate of group health plans of certain religious employers, and later expanded the exemption to include certain nonprofit organizations with religious objections to contraceptive coverage. 78 Fed. Reg. 39871. When this was done, the Government made clear that its objective was to 鈥減rotec[t]鈥 these religious objectors 鈥渇rom having to contract, arrange, pay, or refer for such coverage.鈥 . Those exemptions would be hard to understand if the plaintiffs鈥 objections here were not substantial.
[34] See, ., Oderberg, The Ethics of Co-operation in Wrongdoing, in Modern Moral Philosophy 203鈥228 (A. O鈥橦ear ed. 2004); T. Higgins, Man as Man: The Science and Art of Ethics 353, 355 (1949) (鈥淭he general principles governing cooperation鈥 in wrongdoing鈥., 鈥減hysical activity (or its omission) by which a person assists in the evil act of another who is the principal agent鈥濃斺減resent troublesome difficulties in application鈥); 1 H. Davis, Moral and Pastoral Theology 341 (1935) (Cooperation occurs 鈥渨hen A helps B to accomplish an external act by an act that is not sinful, and without approving of what B does鈥).
[35] The principal dissent makes no effort to reconcile its view about the substantial-burden requirement with our decision in .
[36] Online at http://cbo.gov/publication/45231.
[37] In a related argument, HHS appears to maintain that a plaintiff cannot prevail on a RFRA claim that seeks an exemption from a legal obligation requiring the plaintiff to confer benefits on third parties. Nothing in the text of RFRA or its basic purposes supports giving the Government an entirely free hand to impose burdens on religious exercise so long as those burdens confer a benefit on other individuals. It is certainly true that in applying RFRA 鈥渃ourts must take adequate account of the burdens a requested accommodation may impose on nonbeneficiaries.鈥 v., (applying RLUIPA). That consideration will often inform the analysis of the Government鈥檚 compelling interest and the availability of a less restrictive means of advancing that interest. But it could not reasonably be maintained that any burden on religious exercise, no matter how onerous and no matter how readily the government interest could be achieved through alternative means, is permissible under RFRA so long as the relevant legal obligation requires the religious adherent to confer a benefit on third parties. Otherwise, for example, the Government could decide that all supermarkets must sell alcohol for the convenience of customers (and thereby exclude Muslims with religious objections from owning supermarkets), or it could decide that all restaurants must remain open on Saturdays to give employees an opportunity to earn tips (and thereby exclude Jews with religious objections from owning restaurants). By framing any Government regulation as benefiting a third party, the Government could turn all regulations into entitlements to which nobody could object on religious grounds, rendering RFRA meaningless. In any event, our decision in these cases need not result in any detrimental effect on any third party. As we explain, see , at 43鈥44, the Government can readily arrange for other methods of providing contraceptives, without cost sharing, to employees who are unable to obtain them under their health-insurance plans due to their employers鈥 religious objections.
[38] HHS has concluded that insurers that insure eligible employers opting out of the contraceptive mandate and that are required to pay for contraceptive coverage under the accommodation will not experience an increase in costs because the 鈥渃osts of providing contraceptive coverage are balanced by cost savings from lower pregnancy-related costs and from improvements in women鈥檚 health.鈥 78 Fed. Reg. 39877. With respect to self-insured plans, the regulations establish a mechanism for the eligible employers鈥 third-party administrators to obtain a compensating reduction in the fee paid by insurers to participate in the federally facilitated exchanges. HHS believes that this system will not have a material effect on the funding of the exchanges because the 鈥減ayments for contraceptive services will represent only a small portion of total [federally facilitated exchange] user fees.鈥 at 39882; see 26 CFR 搂54.9815鈥2713A(b)(3).
[39] See n. 9, .
[40] The principal dissent faults us for being 鈥渘oncommital鈥 in refusing to decide a case that is not before us here. , at 30.The less re-strictive approach we describe accommodates the religious beliefs as-serted in these cases, and that is the only question we are permittedto address.
[41] In the principal dissent鈥檚 view, the Government has not had a fair opportunity to address this accommodation, , at 30. n. 27, but the Government itself apparently believes that when it 鈥減rovides an exception to a general rule for secular reasons (or for only certain religious reasons), [it] must explain why extending a comparable exception to a specific plaintiff for religious reasons would undermine its compelling interests.鈥 Brief for the United States as in v., No. 13鈥6827, p. 10, now pending before the Court.
[42] Cf. 42 U. S. C. 搂1396s (Federal 鈥減rogram for distribution of pediatric vaccines鈥 for some uninsured and underinsured children).
[43] HHS highlights certain statements in the opinion in that it regards as supporting its position in these cases. In particular, HHS notes the statement that 鈥淸w]hen followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter of conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes which are binding on others in that activity.鈥 455 U. S., at 261. was a free exercise, not a RFRA, case, and the statement to which HHS points, if taken at face value, is squarely inconsistent with the plain meaning of RFRA. Under RFRA, when followers of a particular religion choose to enter into commercial activity, the Government does not have a free hand in imposing obligations that substantially burden their exercise of religion. Rather, the Government can impose such a burden only if the strict RFRA test is met.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 13鈥354 and 13鈥356
_________________
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND HUMAN SERVICES, et al., PETITIONERS
v.
HOBBY LOBBY STORES, INC., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states courtof appeals for the tenth circuit
and
CONESTOGA WOOD SPECIALTIES CORPORATIONet al., PETITIONERS
v.
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND HUMAN SERVICES, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states courtof appeals for the third circuit
[June 30, 2014]
Justice Kennedy, concurring.
It seems to me appropriate, in joining the Court鈥檚 opinion, to add these few remarks. At the outset it should be said that the Court鈥檚 opinion does not have the breadth and sweep ascribed to it by the respectful and powerful dissent. The Court and the dissent disagree on the proper interpretation of the Religious Freedom and Restoration Act of 1993 (RFRA), but do agree on the purpose of that statute. 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb et seq. It is to ensure that interests in religious freedom are protected. Ante, at 5鈥6; post, at 8鈥9 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting).
In our constitutional tradition, freedom means that all persons have the right to believe or strive to believe in a divine creator and a divine law. For those who choose this course, free exercise is essential in preserving their own dignity and in striving for a self-definition shaped by their religious precepts. Free exercise in this sense implicates more than just freedom of belief. See Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296, 303 (1940) . It means, too, the rightto express those beliefs and to establish one鈥檚 religious(or nonreligious) self-definition in the political, civic, and economic life of our larger community. But in a complex society and an era of pervasive governmental regulation, defining the proper realm for free exercise can be difficult. In these cases the plaintiffs deem it necessary to exercise their religious beliefs within the context of their own closely held, for-profit corporations. They claim protection under RFRA, the federal statute discussed with care and in detail in the Court鈥檚 opinion.
As the Court notes, under our precedents, RFRA imposes a 鈥 鈥榮tringent test.鈥 鈥 Ante, at 6 (quoting City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U. S. 507, 533 (1997) ). The Government must demonstrate that the application of a substantial burden to a person鈥檚 exercise of religion 鈥(1) is in furtherance of a compelling governmental interest; and (2) is the least restrictive means of furthering that compelling governmental interest.鈥 搂2000bb鈥1(b).
As to RFRA鈥檚 first requirement, the Department of Health and Human Services (HHS) makes the case that the mandate serves the Government鈥檚 compelling interest in providing insurance coverage that is necessary to protect the health of female employees, coverage that is significantly more costly than for a male employee. Ante, at 39; see, e.g., Brief for HHS in No. 13鈥354, pp. 14鈥15. There are many medical conditions for which pregnancy is contraindicated. See, e.g., id., at 47. It is important to confirm that a premise of the Court鈥檚 opinion is its assumption that the HHS regulation here at issue furthers a legitimate and compelling interest in the health of female employees. Ante, at 40.
But the Government has not made the second showing required by RFRA, that the means it uses to regulate is the least restrictive way to further its interest. As the Court鈥檚 opinion explains, the record in these casesshows that there is an existing, recognized, workable, and already-implemented framework to provide coverage. That framework is one that HHS has itself devised, that the plaintiffs have not criticized with a specific objection that has been considered in detail by the courts in this litigation, and that is less restrictive than the means challenged by the plaintiffs in these cases. Ante, at 9鈥10, and n. 9, 43鈥44.
The means the Government chose is the imposition of a direct mandate on the employers in these cases. Ante, at 8鈥9. But in other instances the Government has allowed the same contraception coverage in issue here to be provided to employees of nonprofit religious organizations, as an accommodation to the religious objections of those entities. See ante, at 9鈥10, and n. 9, 43鈥44. The accommodation works by requiring insurance companies to cover, without cost sharing, contraception coverage for female employees who wish it. That accommodation equally furthers the Government鈥檚 interest but does not impinge on the plaintiffs鈥 religious beliefs. See ante, at 44.
On this record and as explained by the Court, the Government has not met its burden of showing that it cannot accommodate the plaintiffs鈥 similar religious objections under this established framework. RFRA is inconsis-tent with the insistence of an agency such as HHS on distinguishing between different religious believers鈥攂ur-dening one while accommodating the other鈥攚hen itmay treat both equally by offering both of them the same accommodation.
The parties who were the plaintiffs in the District Courts argue that the Government could pay for the methods that are found objectionable. Brief for Respondents in No. 13鈥354, p. 58. In discussing this alternative, the Court does not address whether the proper response to a legitimate claim for freedom in the health care arena is for the Government to create an additional program. Ante, at 41鈥43. The Court properly does not resolve whether one freedom should be protected by creating incentives for additional government constraints. In these cases, it is the Court鈥檚 understanding that an accommodation may be made to the employers without imposition of a whole new program or burden on the Government. As the Court makes clear, this is not a case where it can be established that it is difficult to accommodate the government鈥檚 interest, and in fact the mechanism for doing so is already in place. Ante, at 43鈥44.
鈥淸T]he American community is today, as it long has been, a rich mosaic of religious faiths.鈥 Town of Greece v. Galloway, 572 U. S. ___, ___ (2014) (Kagan, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 15). Among the reasons the United States is so open, so tolerant, and so free is that no person may be restricted or demeaned by government in exercising his or her religion. Yet neither may that same exercise unduly restrict other persons, such as employees, in protecting their own interests, interests the law deems compelling. In these cases the means to reconcile those two priorities are at hand in the existing accommodation the Government has designed, identified, and used for circumstances closely parallel to those presented here. RFRA requires the Government to use this less restrictive means. As the Court explains, this existing model, designed precisely for this problem, might well suffice to distinguish the instant cases from many others in which it is more difficult and expensive to accommodate a governmental program to countless religious claims based on an alleged statutory right of free exercise. Ante, at 45鈥46.
For these reasons and others put forth by the Court, I join its opinion.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 13鈥354 and 13鈥356
_________________
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND HUMAN SERVICES, et al., PETITIONERS
v.
HOBBY LOBBY STORES, INC., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states courtof appeals for the tenth circuit
and
CONESTOGA WOOD SPECIALTIES CORPORATIONet al., PETITIONERS
v.
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND HUMAN SERVICES, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states courtof appeals for the third circuit
[June 30, 2014]
Justice Ginsburg, with whom Justice Sotomayor joins, and with whom Justice Breyer and Justice Kagan join as to all but Part III鈥揅鈥1, dissenting.
In a decision of startling breadth, the Court holds that commercial enterprises, including corporations, along with partnerships and sole proprietorships, can opt out of any law (saving only tax laws) they judge incompatible with their sincerely held religious beliefs. See ante, at 16鈥49. Compelling governmental interests in uniform compliance with the law, and disadvantages that religion-based opt-outs impose on others, hold no sway, the Court decides, at least when there is a 鈥渓ess restrictive alternative.鈥 And such an alternative, the Court suggests, there always will be whenever, in lieu of tolling an enterprise claiming a religion-based exemption, the government, i.e., the general public, can pick up the tab. See ante, at 41鈥43.[1]
The Court does not pretend that the First Amendment鈥檚 Free Exercise Clause demands religion-based accommodations so extreme, for our decisions leave no doubt on that score. See infra, at 6鈥8. Instead, the Court holds that Congress, in the Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993 (RFRA), 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb et seq., dictated the extraordinary religion-based exemptions today鈥檚 decision endorses. In the Court鈥檚 view, RFRA demands accommodation of a for-profit corporation鈥檚 religious beliefs no matter the impact that accommodation may have on third parties who do not share the corporation owners鈥 religious faith鈥攊n these cases, thousands of women employed by Hobby Lobby and Conestoga or dependents of persons those corporations employ. Persuaded that Congress enacted RFRA to serve a far less radical purpose, and mindful of the havoc the Court鈥檚 judgment can introduce, I dissent.
I
鈥淭he ability of women to participate equally in the economic and social life of the Nation has been facilitated by their ability to control their reproductive lives.鈥 Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U. S. 833, 856 (1992) . Congress acted on that understanding when, as part of a nationwide insurance program intended to be comprehensive, it called for coverage of preventive care responsive to women鈥檚 needs. Carrying out Congress鈥 direction, the Department of Health and Human Services (HHS), in consultation with public health experts, promulgated regulations requiring group health plans to cover all forms of contraception approved by the Food and Drug Administration (FDA). The genesis of this coverage should enlighten the Court鈥檚 resolution of these cases.
A
The Affordable Care Act (ACA), in its initial form, specified three categories of preventive care that health plans must cover at no added cost to the plan participant or beneficiary.[2] Particular services were to be recommended by the U. S. Preventive Services Task Force, an independent panel of experts. The scheme had a large gap, how-ever; it left out preventive services that 鈥渕any women鈥檚 health advocates and medical professionals believe are critically important.鈥 155 Cong. Rec. 28841 (2009) (statement of Sen. Boxer). To correct this oversight, Senator Barbara Mikulski introduced the Women鈥檚 Health Amendment, which added to the ACA鈥檚 minimum coverage requirements a new category of preventive services specific to women鈥檚 health.
Women paid significantly more than men for preventive care, the amendment鈥檚 proponents noted; in fact, cost barriers operated to block many women from obtaining needed care at all. See, e.g., id., at 29070 (statement of Sen. Feinstein) (鈥淲omen of childbearing age spend 68 percent more in out-of-pocket health care costs than men.鈥); id., at 29302 (statement of Sen. Mikulski) (鈥渃opayments are [often] so high that [women] avoid getting [preventive and screening services] in the first place鈥). And increased access to contraceptive services, the sponsors comprehended, would yield important public health gains. See, e.g., id., at 29768 (statement of Sen. Durbin) (鈥淭his bill will expand health insurance coverage to the vast majority of [the 17 million women of reproductive age in the United States who are uninsured] . . . . This expanded access will reduce unintended pregnancies.鈥).
As altered by the Women鈥檚 Health Amendment鈥檚 passage, the ACA requires new insurance plans to include coverage without cost sharing of 鈥渟uch additional preventive care and screenings . . . as provided for in comprehensive guidelines supported by the Health Resources and Services Administration [(HRSA)],鈥 a unit of HHS. 42 U. S. C. 搂300gg鈥13(a)(4). Thus charged, the HRSA developed recommendations in consultation with the Institute of Medicine (IOM). See 77 Fed. Reg. 8725鈥8726 (2012).[3] The IOM convened a group of independent experts, including 鈥渟pecialists in disease prevention [and] women鈥檚 health鈥; those experts prepared a report evaluating the efficacy of a number of preventive services. IOM, Clinical Prevention Services for Women: Closing the Gaps 2 (2011) (hereinafter IOM Report). Consistent with the findings of 鈥淸n]umerous health professional associations鈥 and other organizations, the IOM experts determined that preventive coverage should include the 鈥渇ull range鈥 of FDA-approved contraceptive methods. Id., at 10. See also id., at 102鈥110.
In making that recommendation, the IOM鈥檚 report expressed concerns similar to those voiced by congres-sional proponents of the Women鈥檚 Health Amendment. The report noted the disproportionate burden women carried for comprehensive health services and the adverse health consequences of excluding contraception from preventive care available to employees without cost sharing. See, e.g., id., at 19 (鈥淸W]omen are consistently more likely than men to report a wide range of cost-related barriers to receiving . . . medical tests and treatments and to filling prescriptions for themselves and their families.鈥); id., at 103鈥104, 107 (pregnancy may be contraindicated forwomen with certain medical conditions, for example, some congenital heart diseases, pulmonary hypertension, and Marfan syndrome, and contraceptives may be used to reduce risk of endometrial cancer, among other serious medical conditions); id., at 103 (women with unintended pregnancies are more likely to experience depression and anxiety, and their children face 鈥渋ncreased odds of preterm birth and low birth weight鈥).
In line with the IOM鈥檚 suggestions, the HRSA adopted guidelines recommending coverage of 鈥淸a]ll [FDA-]approved contraceptive methods, sterilization procedures, and patient education and counseling for all women with reproductive capacity.鈥[4] Thereafter, HHS, the Department of Labor, and the Department of Treasury promulgated regulations requiring group health plans to include coverage of the contraceptive services recommended in the HRSA guidelines, subject to certain exceptions, described infra, at 25鈥27.[5] This opinion refers to these regulations as the contraceptive coverage requirement.
B
While the Women鈥檚 Health Amendment succeeded, a countermove proved unavailing. The Senate voted down the so-called 鈥渃onscience amendment,鈥 which would have enabled any employer or insurance provider to deny coverage based on its asserted 鈥渞eligious beliefs or moral convictions.鈥 158 Cong. Rec. S539 (Feb. 9, 2012); see id., at S1162鈥揝1173 (Mar. 1, 2012) (debate and vote).[6] That amendment, Senator Mikulski observed, would have 鈥減u[t] the personal opinion of employers and insurers over the practice of medicine.鈥 Id., at S1127 (Feb. 29, 2012). Rejecting the 鈥渃onscience amendment,鈥 Congress left health care decisions鈥攊ncluding the choice among contraceptive methods鈥攊n the hands of women, with the aid of their health care providers.
II
Any First Amendment Free Exercise Clause claim Hobby Lobby or Conestoga[7] might assert is foreclosed by this Court鈥檚 decision in Employment Div., Dept. of Human Resources of Ore. v. Smith, 494 U. S. 872 (1990) . In Smith, two members of the Native American Church were dismissed from their jobs and denied unemployment benefits because they ingested peyote at, and as an essential element of, a religious ceremony. Oregon law forbade the consumption of peyote, and this Court, relying on that prohibition, rejected the employees鈥 claim that the denial of unemployment benefits violated their free exercise rights. The First Amendment is not offended, Smith held, when 鈥減rohibiting the exercise of religion . . . is not the object of [governmental regulation] but merely the incidental effect of a generally applicable and otherwise valid provision.鈥 Id., at 878; see id., at 878鈥879 (鈥渁n individ-ual鈥檚 religious beliefs [do not] excuse him from compliance with an otherwise valid law prohibiting conduct that the State is free to regulate鈥). The ACA鈥檚 contraceptive coverage requirement applies generally, it is 鈥渙therwise valid,鈥 it trains on women鈥檚 well being, not on the exerciseof religion, and any effect it has on such exercise isincidental.
Even if Smith did not control, the Free Exercise Clause would not require the exemption Hobby Lobby and Conestoga seek. Accommodations to religious beliefs or observances, the Court has clarified, must not significantly impinge on the interests of third parties.[8]
The exemption sought by Hobby Lobby and Conestoga would override significant interests of the corporations鈥 employees and covered dependents. It would deny legions of women who do not hold their employers鈥 beliefs access to contraceptive coverage that the ACA would otherwise secure. See Catholic Charities of Sacramento, Inc. v. Superior Court, 32 Cal. 4th 527, 565, 85 P. 3d 67, 93 (2004) (鈥淲e are unaware of any decision in which . . . [the U. S. Supreme Court] has exempted a religious objector from the operation of a neutral, generally applicable law despite the recognition that the requested exemption would detrimentally affect the rights of third parties.鈥). In sum, with respect to free exercise claims no less than free speech claims, 鈥 鈥榌y]our right to swing your arms ends just where the other man鈥檚 nose begins.鈥 鈥 Chafee, Freedom of Speech in War Time, 32 Harv. L. Rev. 932, 957 (1919).
III
A
Lacking a tenable claim under the Free Exercise Clause, Hobby Lobby and Conestoga rely on RFRA, a statute instructing that 鈥淸g]overnment shall not substantially burden a person鈥檚 exercise of religion even if the burden results from a rule of general applicability鈥 unless the government shows that application of the burden is 鈥渢he least restrictive means鈥 to further a 鈥渃ompelling governmental interest.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb鈥1(a), (b)(2). In RFRA, Congress 鈥渁dopt[ed] a statutory rule comparable to the constitutional rule rejected in Smith.鈥 Gonzales v. O Centro Esp铆rita Beneficente Uni茫o do Vegetal, 546 U. S. 418, 424 (2006) .
RFRA鈥檚 purpose is specific and written into the statute itself. The Act was crafted to 鈥渞estore the compelling interest test as set forth in Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U. S. 398 (1963) and Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U. S. 205 (1972) and to guarantee its application in all cases where free exercise of religion is substantially burdened.鈥 搂2000bb(b)(1).[9] See also 搂2000bb(a)(5) (鈥淸T]he compelling interest test as set forth in prior Federal court rulings isa workable test for striking sensible balances between religious liberty and competing prior governmental in-terests.鈥); ante, at 48 (agreeing that the pre-Smith compelling interest test is 鈥渨orkable鈥 and 鈥渟trike[s] sensible balances鈥).
The legislative history is correspondingly emphatic on RFRA鈥檚 aim. See, e.g., S. Rep. No. 103鈥111, p. 12 (1993) (hereinafter Senate Report) (RFRA鈥檚 purpose was 鈥渙nly to overturn the Supreme Court鈥檚 decision in Smith,鈥 not to 鈥渦nsettle other areas of the law.鈥); 139 Cong. Rec. 26178 (1993) (statement of Sen. Kennedy) (RFRA was 鈥渄esigned to restore the compelling interest test for deciding free exercise claims.鈥). In line with this restorative purpose, Congress expected courts considering RFRA claims to 鈥渓ook to free exercise cases decided prior to Smith for guidance.鈥 Senate Report 8. See also H. R. Rep. No. 103鈥88, pp. 6鈥7 (1993) (hereinafter House Report) (same). In short, the Act reinstates the law as it was prior to Smith, without 鈥渃reat[ing] . . . new rights for any religious practice or for any potential litigant.鈥 139 Cong. Rec. 26178 (statement of Sen. Kennedy). Given the Act鈥檚 moderate purpose, it is hardly surprising that RFRA鈥檚 enactment in 1993 provoked little controversy. See Brief for Senator Murray et al. as Amici Curiae 8 (hereinafter Senators Brief ) (RFRA was approved by a 97-to-3 vote in the Senate and a voice vote in the House of Representatives).
B
Despite these authoritative indications, the Court sees RFRA as a bold initiative departing from, rather than restoring, pre-Smith jurisprudence. See ante, at 6, n. 3, 7, 17, 25鈥27. To support its conception of RFRA as a measure detached from this Court鈥檚 decisions, one that sets a new course, the Court points first to the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act of 2000 (RLUIPA), 42 U. S. C. 搂2000cc et seq., which altered RFRA鈥檚 definition of the term 鈥渆xercise of religion.鈥 RFRA, as originally enacted, defined that term to mean 鈥渢he exercise of religion under the First Amendment to the Constitution.鈥 搂2000bb鈥2(4) (1994 ed.). See ante, at 6鈥7. As amended by RLUIPA, RFRA鈥檚 definition now includes 鈥渁ny exercise of religion, whether or not compelled by, or central to, a system of religious belief.鈥 搂2000bb鈥2(4) (2012 ed.) (cross-referencing 搂2000cc鈥5). That definitional change, according to the Court, reflects 鈥渁n obvious effort to effect a complete separation from First Amendment case law.鈥 Ante, at 7.
The Court鈥檚 reading is not plausible. RLUIPA鈥檚 alteration clarifies that courts should not question the centrality of a particular religious exercise. But the amendment in no way suggests that Congress meant to expand the class of entities qualified to mount religious accommodation claims, nor does it relieve courts of the obligation to inquire whether a government action substantially burdens a religious exercise. See Rasul v. Myers, 563 F. 3d 527, 535 (CADC 2009) (Brown, J., concurring) (鈥淭here is no doubt that RLUIPA鈥檚 drafters, in changing the definition of 鈥榚xercise of religion,鈥 wanted to broaden the scope of the kinds of practices protected by RFRA, not increase the universe of individuals protected by RFRA.鈥); H. R. Rep. No. 106鈥219, p. 30 (1999). See also Gilardi v. United States Dept. of Health and Human Servs., 733 F. 3d 1208, 1211 (CADC 2013) (RFRA, as amended, 鈥減rovides us with no helpful definition of 鈥榚xercise of religion.鈥 鈥); Henderson v. Kennedy, 265 F. 3d 1072, 1073 (CADC 2001) (鈥淭he [RLUIPA] amendments did not alter RFRA鈥檚 basic prohibition that the 鈥榌g]overnment shall not substantially burden a person鈥檚 exercise of religion.鈥 鈥).[10]
Next, the Court highlights RFRA鈥檚 requirement that the government, if its action substantially burdens a person鈥檚 religious observance, must demonstrate that it chose the least restrictive means for furthering a compelling interest. 鈥淸B]y imposing a least-restrictive-means test,鈥 the Court suggests, RFRA 鈥渨ent beyond what was required by our pre-Smith decisions.鈥 Ante, at 17, n. 18 (citing City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U. S. 507 (1997) ). See also ante, at 6, n. 3. But as RFRA鈥檚 statements of purpose and legislative history make clear, Congress intended only to restore, not to scrap or alter, the balancing test as this Court had applied it pre-Smith. See supra, at 8鈥9. See also Senate Report 9 (RFRA鈥檚 鈥渃ompelling interest test generally should not be construed more stringently or more leniently than it was prior to Smith.鈥); House Report 7 (same).
The Congress that passed RFRA correctly read this Court鈥檚 pre-Smith case law as including within the 鈥渃ompelling interest test鈥 a 鈥渓east restrictive means鈥 requirement. See, e.g., Senate Report 5 (鈥淲here [a substantial] burden is placed upon the free exercise of religion, the Court ruled [in Sherbert], the Government must demonstrate that it is the least restrictive means to achieve a compelling governmental interest.鈥). And the view that the pre-Smith test included a 鈥渓east restrictive means鈥 requirement had been aired in testimony before the Senate Judiciary Committee by experts on religious freedom. See, e.g., Hearing on S. 2969 before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 102d Cong., 2d Sess., 78鈥79 (1993) (statement of Prof. Douglas Laycock).
Our decision in City of Boerne, it is true, states that the least restrictive means requirement 鈥渨as not used in the pre-Smith jurisprudence RFRA purported to codify.鈥 See ante, at 6, n. 3, 17, n. 18. As just indicated, however, that statement does not accurately convey the Court鈥檚 pre-Smith jurisprudence. See Sherbert, 374 U. S., at 407 (鈥淸I]t would plainly be incumbent upon the [government] to demonstrate that no alternative forms of regulation would combat [the problem] without infringing First Amendment rights.鈥); Thomas v. Review Bd. of Indiana Employment Security Div., 450 U. S. 707, 718 (1981) (鈥淭he state may justify an inroad on religious liberty by showing that it is the least restrictive means of achieving some compelling state interest.鈥). See also Berg, The New Attacks on Religious Freedom Legislation and Why They Are Wrong, 21 Cardozo L. Rev. 415, 424 (1999) (鈥淚n Boerne, the Court erroneously said that the least restrictive means test 鈥榳as not used in the pre-Smith jurisprudence.鈥 鈥).[11]
C
With RFRA鈥檚 restorative purpose in mind, I turn to the Act鈥檚 application to the instant lawsuits. That task, in view of the positions taken by the Court, requires consideration of several questions, each potentially dispositive of Hobby Lobby鈥檚 and Conestoga鈥檚 claims: Do for-profit corporations rank among 鈥減erson[s]鈥 who 鈥渆xercise . . . religion鈥? Assuming that they do, does the contraceptive coverage requirement 鈥渟ubstantially burden鈥 their religious exercise? If so, is the requirement 鈥渋n furtherance of a compelling government interest鈥? And last, does the requirement represent the least restrictive means for furthering that interest?
Misguided by its errant premise that RFRA moved beyond the pre-Smith case law, the Court falters at each step of its analysis.
1
RFRA鈥檚 compelling interest test, as noted, see supra, at 8, applies to government actions that 鈥渟ubstantially burden a person鈥檚 exercise of religion.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb鈥1(a) (emphasis added). This reference, the Court submits, incorporates the definition of 鈥減erson鈥 found in the Dictionary Act, 1 U. S. C. 搂1, which extends to 鈥渃orporations, companies, associations, firms, partnerships, societies, and joint stock companies, as well as individuals.鈥 See ante, at 19鈥20. The Dictionary Act鈥檚 definition, however, controls only where 鈥渃ontext鈥 does not 鈥渋ndicat[e] otherwise.鈥 搂1. Here, context does so indicate. RFRA speaks of 鈥渁 person鈥檚 exercise of religion.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb鈥1(a) (emphasis added). See also 搂搂2000bb鈥2(4), 2000cc鈥5(7)(a).[12] Whether a corporation qualifies as a 鈥減erson鈥 capable of exercis-ing religion is an inquiry one cannot answer without reference to the 鈥渇ull body鈥 of pre-Smith 鈥渇ree-exercise caselaw.鈥 Gilardi, 733 F. 3d, at 1212. There is in that case law no support for the notion that free exercise rights pertain to for-profit corporations.
Until this litigation, no decision of this Court recognized a for-profit corporation鈥檚 qualification for a religious exemption from a generally applicable law, whether under the Free Exercise Clause or RFRA.[13] The absence of such precedent is just what one would expect, for the exercise of religion is characteristic of natural persons, not artificial legal entities. As Chief Justice Marshall observed nearly two centuries ago, a corporation is 鈥渁n artificial being, invisible, intangible, and existing only in contemplation of law.鈥 Trustees of Dartmouth College v. Woodward, 4 Wheat. 518, 636 (1819). Corporations, Justice Stevens more recently reminded, 鈥渉ave no consciences, no beliefs, no feelings, no thoughts, no desires.鈥 Citizens United v. Federal Election Comm鈥檔, 558 U. S. 310, 466 (2010) (opinion concurring in part and dissenting in part).
The First Amendment鈥檚 free exercise protections, the Court has indeed recognized, shelter churches and other nonprofit religion-based organizations.[14] 鈥淔or many individuals, religious activity derives meaning in large measure from participation in a larger religious community,鈥 and 鈥渇urtherance of the autonomy of religious organizations often furthers individual religious freedom as well.鈥 Corporation of Presiding Bishop of Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints v. Amos, 483 U. S. 327, 342 (1987) (Brennan, J., concurring in judgment). The Court鈥檚 鈥渟pecial solicitude to the rights of religious organizations,鈥 Hosanna-Tabor Evangelical Lutheran Church and School v. EEOC, 565 U. S. ___, ___ (2012) (slip op., at 14), how-ever, is just that. No such solicitude is traditional for com-mercial organizations.[15] Indeed, until today, religious exemptions had never been extended to any entity operating in 鈥渢he commercial, profit-making world.鈥 Amos, 483 U. S., at 337.[16]
The reason why is hardly obscure. Religious organizations exist to foster the interests of persons subscribing to the same religious faith. Not so of for-profit corporations. Workers who sustain the operations of those corporations commonly are not drawn from one religious community. Indeed, by law, no religion-based criterion can restrict the work force of for-profit corporations. See 42 U. S. C. 搂搂2000e(b), 2000e鈥1(a), 2000e鈥2(a); cf. Trans World Airlines, Inc. v. Hardison, 432 U. S. 63 鈥81 (1977) (Title VII requires reasonable accommodation of an employee鈥檚 religious exercise, but such accommodation must not come 鈥渁t the expense of other[ employees]鈥). The distinction between a community made up of believers in the same religion and one embracing persons of diverse beliefs, clear as it is, constantly escapes the Court鈥檚 attention.[17] One can only wonder why the Court shuts this key difference from sight.
Reading RFRA, as the Court does, to require extension of religion-based exemptions to for-profit corporations surely is not grounded in the pre-Smith precedent Congress sought to preserve. Had Congress intended RFRA to initiate a change so huge, a clarion statement to that effect likely would have been made in the legislation. See Whitman v. American Trucking Assns., Inc., 531 U. S. 457, 468 (2001) (Congress does not 鈥渉ide elephants in mouseholes鈥). The text of RFRA makes no such statement and the legislative history does not so much as mention for-profit corporations. See Hobby Lobby Stores, Inc. v. Sebelius, 723 F. 3d 1114, 1169 (CA10 2013) (Briscoe, C. J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (legislative record lacks 鈥渁ny suggestion that Congress foresaw, let alone intended that, RFRA would cover for-profit corporations鈥). See also Senators Brief 10鈥13 (none of thecases cited in House or Senate Judiciary Committeereports accompanying RFRA, or mentioned during floor speeches, recognized the free exercise rights of for-profit corporations).
The Court notes that for-profit corporations may support charitable causes and use their funds for religious ends, and therefore questions the distinction between such corporations and religious nonprofit organizations. See ante, at 20鈥25. See also ante, at 3 (Kennedy, J., concurring) (criticizing the Government for 鈥渄istinguishing between different religious believers鈥攂urdening one while accommodating the other鈥攚hen it may treat both equally by offering both of them the same accommodation鈥).[18] Again, the Court forgets that religious organizations exist to serve a community of believers. For-profit corporations do not fit that bill. Moreover, history is not on the Court鈥檚 side. Recognition of the discrete characters of 鈥渆cclesiastical and lay鈥 corporations dates back to Blackstone, see 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 458 (1765), and was reiterated by this Court centuries before the enactment of the Internal Revenue Code. See Terrett v. Taylor, 9 Cranch 43, 49 (1815) (describing religious corporations); Trustees of Dartmouth College, 4 Wheat., at 645 (discussing 鈥渆leemosynary鈥 corporations, including those 鈥渃reated for the promotion of religion鈥). To reiterate, 鈥渇or-profit corporations are different from religious non-profits in that they use labor to make a profit, rather than to perpetuate [the] religious value[s] [shared by a community of believers].鈥 Gilardi, 733 F. 3d, at 1242 (Edwards, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (emphasis deleted).
Citing Braunfeld v. Brown, 366 U. S. 599 (1961) , the Court questions why, if 鈥渁 sole proprietorship that seeks to make a profit may assert a free-exercise claim, [Hobby Lobby and Conestoga] can鈥檛 . . . do the same?鈥 Ante, at 22 (footnote omitted). See also ante, at 16鈥17. But even accepting, arguendo, the premise that unincorporated business enterprises may gain religious accommodations under the Free Exercise Clause, the Court鈥檚 conclusion is unsound. In a sole proprietorship, the business and its owner are one and the same. By incorporating a business, however, an individual separates herself from the entity and escapes personal responsibility for the entity鈥檚 obligations. One might ask why the separation should hold only when it serves the interest of those who control the corporation. In any event, Braunfeld is hardly impressive authority for the entitlement Hobby Lobby and Conestoga seek. The free exercise claim asserted there was promptly rejected on the merits.
The Court鈥檚 determination that RFRA extends to for-profit corporations is bound to have untoward effects. Although the Court attempts to cabin its language to closely held corporations, its logic extends to corporations of any size, public or private.[19] Little doubt that RFRA claims will proliferate, for the Court鈥檚 expansive notion of corporate personhood鈥攃ombined with its other errorsin construing RFRA鈥攊nvites for-profit entities to seek religion-based exemptions from regulations they deem offensive to their faith.
2
Even if Hobby Lobby and Conestoga were deemed RFRA 鈥減erson[s],鈥 to gain an exemption, they must demonstrate that the contraceptive coverage requirement 鈥渟ubstan-tially burden[s] [their] exercise of religion.鈥 42 U. S. C. 搂2000bb鈥1(a). Congress no doubt meant the modifier 鈥渟ubstantially鈥 to carry weight. In the original draft of RFRA, the word 鈥渂urden鈥 appeared unmodified. The word 鈥渟ubstantially鈥 was inserted pursuant to a clarifying amendment offered by Senators Kennedy and Hatch. See 139 Cong. Rec. 26180. In proposing the amendment, Senator Kennedy stated that RFRA, in accord with the Court鈥檚 pre-Smith case law, 鈥渄oes not require the Government to justify every action that has some effect on religious exercise.鈥 Ibid.
The Court barely pauses to inquire whether any burden imposed by the contraceptive coverage requirement is substantial. Instead, it rests on the Greens鈥 and Hahns鈥 鈥渂elie[f ] that providing the coverage demanded by the HHS regulations is connected to the destruction of an embryo in a way that is sufficient to make it immoral for them to provide the coverage.鈥 Ante, at 36.[20] I agree with the Court that the Green and Hahn families鈥 religious convictions regarding contraception are sincerely held. See Thomas, 450 U. S., at 715 (courts are not to question where an individual 鈥渄r[aws] the line鈥 in defining which practices run afoul of her religious beliefs). See also 42 U. S. C. 搂搂2000bb鈥1(a), 2000bb鈥2(4), 2000cc鈥5(7)(A).[21] But those beliefs, however deeply held, do not suffice to sustain a RFRA claim. RFRA, properly understood, distinguishes between 鈥渇actual allegations that [plaintiffs鈥橾 beliefs are sincere and of a religious nature,鈥 which a court must accept as true, and the 鈥渓egal conclusion . . . that [plaintiffs鈥橾 religious exercise is substantially burdened,鈥 an inquiry the court must undertake. Kaemmerling v. Lappin, 553 F. 3d 669, 679 (CADC 2008).
That distinction is a facet of the pre-Smith jurisprudence RFRA incorporates. Bowen v. Roy, 476 U. S. 693 (1986) , is instructive. There, the Court rejected a free exercise challenge to the Government鈥檚 use of a Native American child鈥檚 Social Security number for purposes of administering benefit programs. Without questioning the sincerity of the father鈥檚 religious belief that 鈥渦se of [his daughter鈥檚 Social Security] number may harm [her] spirit,鈥 the Court concluded that the Government鈥檚 internaluses of that number 鈥減lace[d] [no] restriction on what [the father] may believe or what he may do.鈥 Id., at 699. Recognizing that the father鈥檚 鈥渞eligious views may not accept鈥 the position that the challenged uses concerned only the Government鈥檚 internal affairs, the Court explained that 鈥渇or the adjudication of a constitutional claim, the Constitution, rather than an individual鈥檚 religion, must supply the frame of reference.鈥 Id., at 700鈥701, n. 6. See also Hernandez v. Commissioner, 490 U. S. 680, 699 (1989) (distinguishing between, on the one hand, 鈥渜uestion[s] [of] the centrality of particular beliefs or practices to a faith, or the validity of particular litigants鈥 interpretations of those creeds,鈥 and, on the other, 鈥渨hether the alleged burden imposed [by the challenged government action] is a substantial one鈥). Inattentive to this guidance, today鈥檚 decision elides entirely the distinction between the sincerity of a challenger鈥檚 religious belief and the substantiality of the burden placed on the challenger.
Undertaking the inquiry that the Court forgoes, I would conclude that the connection between the families鈥 religious objections and the contraceptive coverage requirement is too attenuated to rank as substantial. The requirement carries no command that Hobby Lobby or Conestoga purchase or provide the contraceptives they find objectionable. Instead, it calls on the companies covered by the requirement to direct money into undifferentiated funds that finance a wide variety of benefits under comprehensive health plans. Those plans, in order to comply with the ACA, see supra, at 3鈥6, must offer contraceptive coverage without cost sharing, just as they must cover an array of other preventive services.
Importantly, the decisions whether to claim benefits under the plans are made not by Hobby Lobby or Cones-toga, but by the covered employees and dependents, in consultation with their health care providers. Should an employee of Hobby Lobby or Conestoga share the religious beliefs of the Greens and Hahns, she is of course under no compulsion to use the contraceptives in question. But 鈥淸n]o individual decision by an employee and her physician鈥攂e it to use contraception, treat an infection, or have a hip replaced鈥攊s in any meaningful sense [her employer鈥檚] decision or action.鈥 Grote v. Sebelius, 708 F. 3d 850, 865 (CA7 2013) (Rovner, J., dissenting). It is doubtful that Congress, when it specified that burdens must be 鈥渟ubstantia[l],鈥 had in mind a linkage thus interrupted by independent decisionmakers (the woman and her health counselor) standing between the challenged government action and the religious exercise claimed to be infringed. Any decision to use contraceptives made by a woman covered under Hobby Lobby鈥檚 or Conestoga鈥檚 plan will not be propelled by the Government, it will be the wo-man鈥檚 autonomous choice, informed by the physician she consults.
3
Even if one were to conclude that Hobby Lobby and Conestoga meet the substantial burden requirement, the Government has shown that the contraceptive coverage for which the ACA provides furthers compelling interests in public health and women鈥檚 well being. Those interests are concrete, specific, and demonstrated by a wealth of empirical evidence. To recapitulate, the mandated contraception coverage enables women to avoid the health problems unintended pregnancies may visit on them and their children. See IOM Report 102鈥107. The coverage helps safeguard the health of women for whom pregnancy may be hazardous, even life threatening. See Brief for American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists et al. as Amici Curiae 14鈥15. And the mandate secures benefits wholly unrelated to pregnancy, preventing certain cancers, menstrual disorders, and pelvic pain. Brief for Ovarian Cancer National Alliance et al. as Amici Curiae 4, 6鈥7, 15鈥16; 78 Fed. Reg. 39872 (2013); IOM Report 107.
That Hobby Lobby and Conestoga resist coverage for only 4 of the 20 FDA-approved contraceptives does not lessen these compelling interests. Notably, the corporations exclude intrauterine devices (IUDs), devices significantly more effective, and significantly more expensive than other contraceptive methods. See id., at 105.[22] Moreover, the Court鈥檚 reasoning appears to permit commercial enterprises like Hobby Lobby and Conestoga to exclude from their group health plans all forms of contraceptives. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 38鈥39 (counsel for Hobby Lobby acknowledged that his 鈥渁rgument . . . would apply just as well if the employer said 鈥榥o contraceptives鈥 鈥 (internal quotation marks added)).
Perhaps the gravity of the interests at stake has led the Court to assume, for purposes of its RFRA analysis, that the compelling interest criterion is met in these cases. See ante, at 40.[23] It bears note in this regard that the cost of an IUD is nearly equivalent to a month鈥檚 full-time pay for workers earning the minimum wage, Brief for Guttmacher Institute et al. as Amici Curiae 16; that almost one-third of women would change their contraceptive method if costs were not a factor, Frost & Darroch, Factors Associated With Contraceptive Choice and Inconsistent Method Use, United States, 2004, 40 Perspectives on Sexual & Reproductive Health 94, 98 (2008); and that only one-fourth of women who request an IUD actually have one inserted after finding out how expensive it would be, Gariepy, Simon, Patel, Creinin, & Schwarz, The Impact of Out-of-Pocket Expense on IUD Utilization Among Women With Private Insurance, 84 Contraception e39, e40 (2011). See also Eisenberg, supra, at S60 (recent study found that women who face out-of-pocket IUD costs in excess of $50 were 鈥11-times less likely to obtain an IUD than women who had to pay less than $50鈥); Postlethwaite, Trussell, Zoolakis, Shabear, & Petitti, A Comparison of Contraceptive Procurement Pre- and Post-Benefit Change, 76 Contraception 360, 361鈥362 (2007) (when one health system eliminated patient cost sharing for IUDs, use of this form of contraception more than doubled).
Stepping back from its assumption that compelling interests support the contraceptive coverage requirement, the Court notes that small employers and grandfathered plans are not subject to the requirement. If there is a compelling interest in contraceptive coverage, the Court suggests, Congress would not have created these exclusions. See ante, at 39鈥40.
Federal statutes often include exemptions for small employers, and such provisions have never been held to undermine the interests served by these statutes. See, e.g., Family and Medical Leave Act of 1993, 29 U. S. C. 搂2611(4)(A)(i) (applicable to employers with 50 or more employees); Age Discrimination in Employment Act of 1967, 29 U. S. C. 搂630(b) (originally exempting employers with fewer than 50 employees, 81Stat. 605, the statute now governs employers with 20 or more employees); Americans With Disabilities Act, 42 U. S. C. 搂12111(5)(A) (applicable to employers with 15 or more employees); Title VII, 42 U. S. C. 搂2000e(b) (originally exempting employers with fewer than 25 employees, see Arbaugh v. Y & H Corp., 546 U. S. 500 , n. 2 (2006), the statute now governs employers with 15 or more employees).
The ACA鈥檚 grandfathering provision, 42 U. S. C. 搂18011, allows a phasing-in period for compliance with a number of the Act鈥檚 requirements (not just the contraceptive coverage or other preventive services provisions). Once specified changes are made, grandfathered status ceases. See 45 CFR 搂147.140(g). Hobby Lobby鈥檚 own situation is illustrative. By the time this litigation commenced, Hobby Lobby did not have grandfathered status. Asked why by the District Court, Hobby Lobby鈥檚 counsel explained that the 鈥済randfathering requirements mean that you can鈥檛 make a whole menu of changes to your plan that involve things like the amount of co-pays, the amount of co-insurance, deductibles, that sort of thing.鈥 App. in No. 13鈥354, pp. 39鈥40. Counsel acknowledged that, 鈥渏ust because of economic realities, our plan has to shift over time. I mean, insurance plans, as everyone knows, shif[t] over time.鈥 Id., at 40.[24] The percentage of employees in grandfathered plans is steadily declining, having dropped from 56% in 2011 to 48% in 2012 to 36% in 2013. Kaiser Family Foundation & Health Research & Educ. Trust, Employer Benefits 2013 Annual Survey 7, 196. In short, far from ranking as a categorical exemption, the grandfathering provision is 鈥渢emporary, intended to be a means for gradually transitioning employers into mandatory coverage.鈥 Gilardi, 733 F. 3d, at 1241 (Edwards, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
The Court ultimately acknowledges a critical point: RFRA鈥檚 application 鈥渕ust take adequate account of the burdens a requested accommodation may impose on nonbeneficiaries.鈥 Ante, at 42, n. 37 (quoting Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U. S. 709, 720 (2005) ; emphasis added). No tradition, and no prior decision under RFRA, allows a religion-based exemption when the accommodation would be harmful to others鈥攈ere, the very persons the contraceptive coverage requirement was designed to protect. Cf. supra, at 7鈥8; Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U. S. 158, 177 (1944) (Jackson, J., dissenting) (鈥淸The] limitations which of necessity bound religious freedom . . . begin to operate whenever activities begin to affect or collide with liberties of others or of the public.鈥).
4
After assuming the existence of compelling government interests, the Court holds that the contraceptive coverage requirement fails to satisfy RFRA鈥檚 least restrictive means test. But the Government has shown that there is no less restrictive, equally effective means that would both (1) satisfy the challengers鈥 religious objections to providing insurance coverage for certain contraceptives (which they believe cause abortions); and (2) carry out the objective of the ACA鈥檚 contraceptive coverage requirement, to ensure that women employees receive, at no cost to them, the preventive care needed to safeguard their health and well being. A 鈥渓east restrictive means鈥 cannot require employees to relinquish benefits accorded them by federal law in order to ensure that their commercial employers can adhere unreservedly to their religious tenets. See supra, at 7鈥8, 27.[25]
Then let the government pay (rather than the employees who do not share their employer鈥檚 faith), the Court suggests. 鈥淭he most straightforward [alternative],鈥 the Court asserts, 鈥渨ould be for the Government to assume the cost of providing . . . contraceptives . . . to any women who are unable to obtain them under their health-insurance policies due to their employers鈥 religious objections.鈥 Ante, at 41. The ACA, however, requires coverage of preventive services through the existing employer-based system of health insurance 鈥渟o that [employees] face minimal logistical and administrative obstacles.鈥 78 Fed. Reg. 39888. Impeding women鈥檚 receipt of benefits 鈥渂y requiring them to take steps to learn about, and to sign up for, a new [government funded and administered] health benefit鈥 was scarcely what Congress contemplated. Ibid. More-over, Title X of the Public Health Service Act, 42 U. S. C. 搂300 et seq., 鈥渋s the nation鈥檚 only dedicated source of federal funding for safety net family planning services.鈥 Brieffor National Health Law Program et al. as Amici Curiae 23. 鈥淪afety net programs like Title X are not designed to absorb the unmet needs of . . . insured individuals.鈥 Id., at 24. Note, too, that Congress declined to write into law the preferential treatment Hobby Lobby and Conestoga describe as a less restrictive alternative. See supra, at 6.
And where is the stopping point to the 鈥渓et the government pay鈥 alternative? Suppose an employer鈥檚 sincerely held religious belief is offended by health coverage of vaccines, or paying the minimum wage, see Tony and Susan Alamo Foundation v. Secretary of Labor, 471 U. S. 290, 303 (1985) , or according women equal pay for substantially similar work, see Dole v. Shenandoah Baptist Church, 899 F. 2d 1389, 1392 (CA4 1990)? Does it rank as a less restrictive alternative to require the government to provide the money or benefit to which the employer hasa religion-based objection?[26] Because the Court cannot easily answer that question, it proposes something else: Extension to commercial enterprises of the accommodation already afforded to nonprofit religion-based organizations. See ante, at 3鈥4, 9鈥10, 43鈥45. 鈥淎t a minimum,鈥 according to the Court, such an approach would not 鈥渋mpinge on [Hobby Lobby鈥檚 and Conestoga鈥檚] religious belief.鈥 Ante, at 44. I have already discussed the 鈥渟pecial solicitude鈥 generally accorded nonprofit religion-based organizations that exist to serve a community of believers, solicitude never before accorded to commercial enterprises comprising employees of diverse faiths. See supra, at 14鈥17.
Ultimately, the Court hedges on its proposal to align for-profit enterprises with nonprofit religion-based organizations. 鈥淲e do not decide today whether [the] approach [the opinion advances] complies with RFRA for purposes of all religious claims.鈥 Ante, at 44. Counsel for Hobby Lobby was similarly noncommittal. Asked at oral argument whether the Court-proposed alternative was acceptable,[27] counsel responded: 鈥淲e haven鈥檛 been offered that accommodation, so we haven鈥檛 had to decide what kind of objection, if any, we would make to that.鈥 Tr. of Oral Arg. 86鈥87.
Conestoga suggests that, if its employees had to acquire and pay for the contraceptives (to which the corporation objects) on their own, a tax credit would qualify as a less restrictive alternative. See Brief for Petitioners in No. 13鈥356, p. 64. A tax credit, of course, is one variety of 鈥渓et the government pay.鈥 In addition to departing from the existing employer-based system of health insurance, Conestoga鈥檚 alternative would require a woman to reach into her own pocket in the first instance, and it would do nothing for the woman too poor to be aided by a tax credit.
In sum, in view of what Congress sought to accomplish, i.e., comprehensive preventive care for women furnished through employer-based health plans, none of the proffered alternatives would satisfactorily serve the compelling interests to which Congress responded.
IV
Among the pathmarking pre-Smith decisions RFRA preserved is United States v. Lee, 455 U. S. 252 (1982) . Lee, a sole proprietor engaged in farming and carpentry, was a member of the Old Order Amish. He sincerely believed that withholding Social Security taxes from his employees or paying the employer鈥檚 share of such taxes would violate the Amish faith. This Court held that, although the obligations imposed by the Social Security system conflicted with Lee鈥檚 religious beliefs, the burden was not unconstitutional. Id., at 260鈥261. See also id., at 258 (recognizing the important governmental interest in providing a 鈥渘ationwide . . . comprehensive insurance system with a variety of benefits available to all participants, with costs shared by employers and employees鈥).[28] The Government urges that Lee should control the challenges brought by Hobby Lobby and Conestoga. See Brief for Respondents in No. 13鈥356, p. 18. In contrast, today鈥檚 Court dismisses Lee as a tax case. See ante, at 46鈥47. Indeed, it was a tax case and the Court in Lee homed in on 鈥淸t]he difficulty in attempting to accommodate religious beliefs in the area of taxation.鈥 455 U. S., at 259.
But the Lee Court made two key points one cannot confine to tax cases. 鈥淲hen followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a matter of choice,鈥 the Court observed, 鈥渢he limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter of conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on statutory schemes which are binding on others in that activity.鈥 Id., at 261. The statutory scheme of employer-based comprehensive health coverage involved in these cases is surely binding on others engaged in the same trade or business as the corporate challengers here, Hobby Lobby and Conestoga. Further, the Court recognized in Lee that allowing a religion-based exemption to a commercial employer would 鈥渙perat[e] to impose the employer鈥檚 religious faith on the employees.鈥 Ibid.[29] No doubt the Greens and Hahns and all who share their beliefs may decline to acquire for themselves the contraceptives in question. But that choice may not be imposed on employees who hold other beliefs. Working for Hobby Lobby or Conestoga, in other words, should not deprive employees of the preventive care available to workers at the shop next door,[30] at least in the absence of directions from the Legislature or Administration to do so.
Why should decisions of this order be made by Congress or the regulatory authority, and not this Court? Hobby Lobby and Conestoga surely do not stand alone as commercial enterprises seeking exemptions from generally applicable laws on the basis of their religious beliefs. See, e.g., Newman v. Piggie Park Enterprises, Inc., 256 F. Supp. 941, 945 (SC 1966) (owner of restaurant chain refused to serve black patrons based on his religious beliefs opposing racial integration), aff鈥檇 in relevant part and rev鈥檇 in part on other grounds, 377 F. 2d 433 (CA4 1967), aff鈥檇 and modified on other grounds, 390 U. S. 400 (1968) ; In re Minnesota ex rel. McClure, 370 N. W. 2d 844, 847 (Minn. 1985) (born-again Christians who owned closely held, for-profit health clubs believed that the Bible proscribed hiring or retaining an 鈥渋ndividua[l] living with but not married to a person of the opposite sex,鈥 鈥渁 young, single woman working without her father鈥檚 consent or a married woman working without her husband鈥檚 consent,鈥 and any person 鈥渁ntagonistic to the Bible,鈥 including 鈥渇ornicators and homosexuals鈥 (internal quotation marks omitted)), appeal dismissed, 478 U. S. 1015 (1986) ; Elane Photography, LLC v. Willock, 2013鈥揘MSC鈥040, ___ N. M. ___, 309 P. 3d 53 (for-profit photography business owned by a husband and wife refused to photograph a lesbian couple鈥檚 commitment ceremony based on the religious beliefs of the company鈥檚 owners), cert. denied, 572 U. S. ___ (2014). Would RFRA require exemptions in cases of this ilk? And if not, how does the Court divine which religious beliefs are worthy of accommodation, and which are not? Isn鈥檛 the Court disarmed from making such a judgment given its recognition that 鈥渃ourts must not presume to determine . . . the plausibility of a religious claim鈥? Ante, at 37.
Would the exemption the Court holds RFRA demands for employers with religiously grounded objections to the use of certain contraceptives extend to employers with religiously grounded objections to blood transfusions (Jehovah鈥檚 Witnesses); antidepressants (Scientologists); medications derived from pigs, including anesthesia, intravenous fluids, and pills coated with gelatin (certain Muslims, Jews, and Hindus); and vaccinations (Christian Scientists, among others)?[31] According to counsel for Hobby Lobby, 鈥渆ach one of these cases . . . would have to be evaluated on its own . . . apply[ing] the compelling interest-least restrictive alternative test.鈥 Tr. of Oral Arg. 6. Not much help there for the lower courts bound by today鈥檚 decision.
The Court, however, sees nothing to worry about. Today鈥檚 cases, the Court concludes, are 鈥渃oncerned solely with the contraceptive mandate. Our decision should not be understood to hold that an insurance-coverage mandate must necessarily fall if it conflicts with an employer鈥檚 religious beliefs. Other coverage requirements, such as immunizations, may be supported by different interests (for example, the need to combat the spread of infectious diseases) and may involve different arguments about the least restrictive means of providing them.鈥 Ante, at 46. But the Court has assumed, for RFRA purposes, that the interest in women鈥檚 health and well being is compelling and has come up with no means adequate to serve that interest, the one motivating Congress to adopt the Women鈥檚 Health Amendment.
There is an overriding interest, I believe, in keeping the courts 鈥渙ut of the business of evaluating the relative merits of differing religious claims,鈥 Lee, 455 U. S., at 263, n. 2 (Stevens, J., concurring in judgment), or the sincerity with which an asserted religious belief is held. Indeed, approving some religious claims while deeming others unworthy of accommodation could be 鈥減erceived as favoring one religion over another,鈥 the very 鈥渞isk the Establishment Clause was designed to preclude.鈥 Ibid. The Court, I fear, has ventured into a minefield, cf. Spencer v. World Vision, Inc., 633 F. 3d 723, 730 (CA9 2010) (O鈥橲cannlain, J., concurring), by its immoderate reading of RFRA. I would confine religious exemptions under that Act to organizations formed 鈥渇or a religious purpose,鈥 鈥渆ngage[d] primarily in carrying out that religious purpose,鈥 and not 鈥渆ngaged . . . substantially in the exchange of goods or services for money beyond nominal amounts.鈥 See id., at 748 (Kleinfeld, J., concurring).
*鈥冣赌*鈥冣赌*
For the reasons stated, I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Tenth Circuit and affirm the judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit.
Notes
[1] The Court insists it has held none of these things, for another less restrictive alternative is at hand: extending an existing accommodation, currently limited to religious nonprofit organizations, to encompass commercial enterprises. See at 3鈥4. With that accommodation extended, the Court asserts, 鈥渨omen would still be entitled to all [Food and Drug Administration]-approved contraceptives without cost sharing.鈥 at 4. In the end, however, the Court is not so sure. In stark contrast to the Court鈥檚 initial emphasis on this accommodation, it ultimately declines to decide whether the highlighted accommodation is even lawful. See at 44 (鈥淲e do not decide today whether an approach of this type complies with RFRA . . . .鈥).
[2] See 鈥13(a)(1)鈥(3) (group health plans must provide coverage, without cost sharing, for (1) certain 鈥渆vidence-based items or services鈥 recommended by the U. S. Preventive Services Task Force; (2) immunizations recommended by an advisory committee of the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention; and (3) 鈥渨ith respect to infants, children, and adolescents, evidence-informed preventive care and screenings provided for in the comprehensive guidelines supported by the Health Resources and Services Administration鈥).
[3] The IOM is an arm of the National Academy of Sciences, an organization Congress established 鈥渇or the explicit purpose of furnishing advice to the Government.鈥 v. , , n. 11 (1989) (internal quotation marks omitted).
[4] HRSA, HHS, Women鈥檚 Preventive Services Guidelines, available at http://www.hrsa.gov/womensguidelines/ (all Internet materials as visited June 27, 2014, and available in Clerk of Court鈥檚 case file), reprinted in App. to Brief for Petitioners in No. 13鈥354, pp. 43鈥44a. See also 77 Fed. Reg. 8725鈥8726 (2012).
[5] 45 CFR 搂147.130(a)(1)(iv) (2013) (HHS); 29 CFR 搂2590.715鈥2713(a)(1)(iv) (2013) (Labor); 26 CFR 搂54.9815鈥2713(a)(1)(iv) (2013) (Treasury).
[6] Separating moral convictions from religious beliefs would be of questionable legitimacy. See v. , 鈥358 (1970) (Harlan, J., concurring in result).
[7] As the Court explains, see at 11鈥16, these cases arise from two separate lawsuits, one filed by Hobby Lobby, its affiliated business (Mardel), and the family that operates these businesses (the Greens); the other filed by Conestoga and the family that owns and controls that business (the Hahns). Unless otherwise specified, this opinion refers to the respective groups of plaintiffs as Hobby Lobby and Conestoga.
[8] See v. , (鈥淭his case, of course, is not one in which any harm to the physical or mental health of the child or to the public safety, peace, order, or welfare has been demonstrated or may be properly inferred.鈥); v. , (invalidating state statute requiring employers to accommodate an employee鈥檚 Sabbath observance where that statute failed to take into account the burden such an accommodation would impose on the employer or other employees). Notably, in construing the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act of 2000 (RLUIPA), the Court has cautioned that 鈥渁dequate account鈥 must be taken of 鈥渢he burdens a requested accommodation may impose on nonbeneficiaries.鈥 v. , ; see at 722 (鈥渁n accommodation must be measured so that it does not override other significant interests鈥). A balanced approach is all the more in order when the Free Exercise Clause itself is at stake, not a statute designed to promote accommodation to religious beliefs and practices.
[9] Under and , the Court 鈥渞equir[ed] the government to justify any substantial burden on religiously motivated conduct by a compelling state interest and by means narrowly tailored to achieve that interest.鈥 v. , (O鈥機onnor, J., concurring injudgment).
[10] RLUIPA, the Court notes, includes a provision directing that 鈥淸t]his chapter [, RLUIPA] shall be construed in favor of a broad protection of religious exercise, to the maximum extent permitted by the terms of [the Act] and the Constitution.鈥 鈥3(g); see at 6鈥7, 26. RFRA incorporates RLUIPA鈥檚 definition of 鈥渆xercise of religion,鈥 as RLUIPA does, but contains no omnibus rule of construction governing the statute in its entirety.
[11] The Court points out that I joined the majority opinion in and did not then question the statement that 鈥渓east restrictive means . . . was not used [pre-].鈥 at 17, n. 18. Concerning that observation, I remind my colleagues of Justice Jackson鈥檚 sage comment: 鈥淚 see no reason why I should be consciously wrong today because I was unconsciously wrong yesterday.鈥 v. , 鈥640 (1948) (dissenting opinion).
[12] As earlier explained, see at 10鈥11, RLUIPA鈥檚 amendment of the definition of 鈥渆xercise of religion鈥 does not bear the weight the Court places on it. Moreover, it is passing strange to attribute to RLUIPA any purpose to cover entities other than 鈥渞eligious assembl[ies] or institution[s].鈥 . But cf. at 26. That law applies to land-use regulation. 搂2000cc(a)(1). To permit commercial enterprises to challenge zoning and other land-use regulations under RLUIPA would 鈥渄ramatically expand the statute鈥檚 reach鈥 and deeply intrude on local prerogatives, contrary to Congress鈥 intent. Brief for National League of Cities et al. as 26.
[13] The Court regards v., , as 鈥渟uggest[ing] . . . that for-profit corporations possess [free-exercise] rights.鈥 at 26鈥27. See also at 21, n. 21. The suggestion is barely there. True, one of the five challengers to the Sunday closing law assailed in was a corporation owned by four Orthodox Jews. The other challengers were human individuals, not artificial, law-created entities, so there was no need to determine whether the corporation could institute the litigation. Accordingly, the plurality stated it could pretermit the question 鈥渨hether appellees ha[d] standing鈥 because v. , , which upheld a similar closing law, was fatal to their claim on the merits. 366 U. S., at 631.
[14] See, v. , 565 U. S. ___ (2012); v. , ; v. , ; v. , .
[15] Typically, Congress has accorded to organizations religious in character religion-based exemptions from statutes of general application. 鈥1(a) (Title VII exemption from prohibition against employment discrimination based on religion for 鈥渁 religious corporation, association, educational institution, or society with respect to the employment of individuals of a particular religion to perform work connected with the carrying on . . . of its activities鈥); (parallel exemption in Americans With Disabilities Act of 1990). It can scarcely be maintained that RFRA enlarges these exemptions to allow Hobby Lobby and Conestoga to hire only persons who share the religious beliefs of the Greens or Hahns. Nor does the Court suggest otherwise. Cf. at 28.
[16] That is not to say that a category of plaintiffs, such as resident aliens, may bring RFRA claims only if this Court expressly 鈥渁ddressed their [free-exercise] rights before .鈥 at 27. Continuing with the Court鈥檚 example, resident aliens, unlike corporations, are flesh-and-blood individuals who plainly count as persons sheltered by the , see v. , (citing v. , ), and , RFRA.
[17] I part ways with on the context relevant here. He sees it as the employers鈥 鈥渆xercise [of] their religious beliefs within the context of their own closely held, for-profit corporations.鈥 at 2 (concurring opinion). See also at 45鈥46 (opinion of the Court) (similarly concentrating on religious faith of employers without reference to the different beliefs and liberty interests of employees). I see as the relevant context the employers鈥 asserted right to exercise religion within a nationwide program designed to protect against health hazards employees who do not subscribe to their employers鈥 religious beliefs.
[18] According to the Court, the Government 鈥渃oncedes鈥 that 鈥渘onprofit corporation[s]鈥 are protected by RFRA. at 19. See also at 20, 24, 30. That is not an accurate description of the Government鈥檚 position, which encompasses only 鈥渃hurches,鈥 鈥 institutions,鈥 and 鈥 non-profits.鈥 Brief for Respondents in No. 13鈥356, p. 28 (emphasis added). See also Reply Brief in No. 13鈥354, p. 8 (鈥淩FRA incorporates the longstanding and common-sense distinction between religious organizations, which sometimes have been accorded accommodations under generally applicable laws in recognition of their accepted religious character, and for-profit corporations organized to do business in the commercial world.鈥).
[19] The Court does not even begin to explain how one might go about ascertaining the religious scruples of a corporation where shares are sold to the public. No need to speculate on that, the Court says, for 鈥渋t seems unlikely鈥 that large corporations 鈥渨ill often assert RFRA claims.鈥 at 29. Perhaps so, but as Hobby Lobby鈥檚 case demonstrates, such claims are indeed pursued by large corporations, employing thousands of persons of different faiths, whose ownership is not diffuse. 鈥淐losely held鈥 is not synonymous with 鈥渟mall.鈥 Hobby Lobby is hardly the only enterprise of sizable scale that is family owned or closely held. For example, the family-owned candy giant Mars, Inc., takes in $33 billion in revenues and has some 72,000 employees, and closely held Cargill, Inc., takes in more than $136 billion in reve-nues and employs some 140,000 persons. See Forbes, America鈥檚 Largest Private Companies 2013, available at http://www.forbes.com/largest-private-companies/.
[20] The Court dismisses the argument, advanced by some , that the $2,000-per-employee tax charged to certain employers that fail to provide health insurance is less than the average cost of offering health insurance, noting that the Government has not provided the statistics that could support such an argument. See at 32鈥34. The Court overlooks, however, that it is not the Government鈥檚 obligation to prove that an asserted burden is substantial. Instead, it is incumbent upon plaintiffs to demonstrate, in support of a RFRA claim, the substantial-ity of the alleged burden.
[21] The Court levels a criticism that is as wrongheaded as can be. In no way does the dissent 鈥渢ell the plaintiffs that their beliefs are flawed.鈥 at 37. Right or wrong in this domain is a judgment no Member of this Court, or any civil court, is authorized or equipped to make. What the Court must decide is not 鈥渢he plausibility of a religious claim,鈥 at 37 (internal quotation marks omitted), but whether accommodating that claim risks depriving others of rights accorded them by the laws of the United States. See at 7鈥8; , at 27.
[22] IUDs, which are among the most reliable forms of contraception, generally cost women more than $1,000 when the expenses of the office visit and insertion procedure are taken into account. See Eisenberg, McNicholas, & Peipert, Cost as a Barrier to Long-Acting Reversible Contraceptive (LARC) Use in Adolescents, 52 J. Adolescent Health S59, S60 (2013). See also Winner et al., Effectiveness of Long-Acting Reversible Contraception, 366 New Eng. J. Medicine 1998, 1999 (2012).
[23] Although the Court鈥檚 opinion makes this assumption grudgingly, see at 39鈥40, one Member of the majority recognizes, without reservation, that 鈥渢he [contraceptive coverage] mandate serves the Government鈥檚 compelling interest in providing insurance coverage that is necessary to protect the health of female employees.鈥 at 2 (opinion of , J.).
[24] Hobby Lobby鈥檚 National Religious Broadcasters similarly states that, 鈥淸g]iven the nature of employers鈥 needs to meet changing economic and staffing circumstances, and to adjust insurance coverage accordingly, the actual benefit of the 鈥榞randfather鈥 exclusion is and transitory at best.鈥 Brief for National Religious Broadcasters as in No. 13鈥354, p. 28.
[25] As the Court made clear in , the government鈥檚 license to grant religion-based exemptions from generally applicable laws is constrained by the Establishment Clause. 544 U. S., at 720鈥722. 鈥淸W]e are a cosmopolitan nation made up of people of almost every conceivable religious preference,鈥 , 366 U. S., at 606, a 鈥渞ich mosaic of religious faiths,鈥 v. , 572 U. S. ___, ___ (2014) (, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 15). Consequently, one person鈥檚 right to free exercise must be kept in harmony with the rights of her fellow citizens, and 鈥渟ome religious practices [must] yield to the common good.鈥 v. , .
[26] Cf. v. , (in context of Speech Clause challenge to a content-based speech restriction, courts must determine 鈥渨hether the challenged regulation is the least restrictive means among , effective alternatives鈥 (emphasis added)).
[27] On brief, Hobby Lobby and Conestoga barely addressed the extension solution, which would bracket commercial enterprises with nonprofit religion-based organizations for religious accommodations purposes. The hesitation is understandable, for challenges to the adequacy of the accommodation accorded religious nonprofit organizations are currently . See, v. , ___ F. Supp. 2d ___, 2013 WL 6839900 (Colo., Dec. 27, 2013), injunction pending appeal granted, 571 U. S. ___ (2014). At another point in today鈥檚 decision, the Court refuses to consider an argument neither 鈥渞aised below [nor] advanced in this Court by any party,鈥 giving Hobby Lobby and Conestoga 鈥淸no] opportunity to respond to [that] novel claim.鈥 at 33. Yet the Court is content to decide this case (and this case only) on the ground that HHS could make an accommodation never suggested in the parties鈥 presentations. RFRA cannot sensibly be read to 鈥渞equir[e] the government to . . . refute each and every conceivable alternative regulation,鈥 v. , 638 F. 3d 1274, 1289 (CA10 2011), especially where the alternative on which the Court seizes was not pressed by any challenger.
[28] As a sole proprietor, Lee was subject to personal liability for violating the law of general application he opposed. His claim to a religion-based exemption would have been even thinner had he conducted his business as a corporation, thus avoiding personal liability.
[29] Congress amended the Social Security Act in response to . The amended statute permits Amish sole proprietors and partnerships (but not Amish-owned corporations) to obtain an exemption from the obligation to pay Social Security taxes only for employees who are co-religionists and who likewise seek an exemption and agree to give up their Social Security benefits. See , (b)(1). Thus, employers with sincere religious beliefs have no right to a religion-based exemption that would deprive employees of Social Security benefits without the employee鈥檚 consent鈥攁n exemption analogous to the one Hobby Lobby and Conestoga seek here.
[30] Cf. v. , (disallowing religion-based exemption that 鈥渨ould undoubtedly give [the commercial enterprise seeking the exemption] and similar organizations an advantage over their competitors鈥).
[31] Religious objections to immunization programs are not hypothetical. See v. , ___ F. Supp. 2d ___, 2014 WL 2547584 (EDNY, June 5, 2014) (dismissing free exercise challenges to New York鈥檚 vaccination practices); Liberty Counsel, Compulsory Vaccinations Threaten Religious Freedom (2007), available at
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 13鈥354 and 13鈥356
_________________
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND HUMAN SERVICES, et al., PETITIONERS
v.
HOBBY LOBBY STORES, INC., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states courtof appeals for the tenth circuit
and
CONESTOGA WOOD SPECIALTIES CORPORATIONet al., PETITIONERS
v.
SYLVIA BURWELL, SECRETARY OF HEALTHAND HUMAN SERVICES, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states courtof appeals for the third circuit
[June 30, 2014]
Justice Breyer and Justice Kagan, dissenting.
We agree with Justice Ginsburg that the plaintiffs鈥 challenge to the contraceptive coverage requirement fails on the merits. We need not and do not decide whether either for-profit corporations or their owners may bring claims under the Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993. Accordingly, we join all but Part III鈥揅鈥1 of Justice Ginsburg鈥檚 dissenting opinion.