Table of Contents
Video Lesson: Content-based and Viewpoint-based discrimination

First Amendment for College Administrators
Lesson 3: Public Forums and Your Campus
Video 3: Content-based and Viewpoint-based discrimination

Video Transcript
What does it mean for a regulation of speech to be content based? What does it mean for a regulation to be viewpoint based? Let鈥檚 start with what we鈥檝e already learned: If your school prohibits students from posting flyers on the walls of, say, the Natural Science building, that鈥檚 content neutral - no matter what the flyers says, students just aren鈥檛 allowed to post there. But if you only prohibit students from posting, for instance, political flyers on those walls 鈥 well, then, whether students are allowed to post or not depends on the topic the flyers discuss. That鈥檚 a content-based regulation. Now here鈥檚 another wrinkle: If you permit political flyers, but only from one party, that鈥檚 viewpoint-based discrimination.
As we touched on in the last video, instead of just policing when, where, or how people speak on campus, content-based restrictions tell people they can or cannot speak based on what, exactly, they鈥檙e talking about. While public colleges and universities may have a lot of leeway to impose time, place, and manner restrictions on speech, schools鈥 power to regulate speech wanes significantly when their regulations depend on the content of speech. And, as I鈥檒l explain in a bit, schools have no power at all to restrict expression based solely on a speaker鈥檚 viewpoint.
The Supreme Court has held that a regulation of speech is content-based if it 鈥渁pplies to particular speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed.鈥 From 2015 until just recently, the Court gifted us with a simple method for discerning content-based regulations, from a case that also served as a helpful mnemonic device: Reed v. Town of Gilbert. In Reed, the court held that if you have read a sign to enforce a regulation, that regulation is content based.
That鈥檚 still a pretty good rule of thumb, and will be helpful to you in most cases. In Reed, a pastor challenged town sign regulations that applied differently depending on whether a sign鈥檚 message was ideological, political or directional. The Court held that these distinctions, which depended on the message signs conveyed, rendered the regulations content-based. Since Reed, the Court has added a little bit of nuance: Now, if the only reason you鈥檙e reading the sign is to determine whether it鈥檚 about the place it鈥檚 posted on (to make an on-premise/off-premise distinction), that, per the Court, is more like a an 鈥渙rdinary time, place, or manner restriction.鈥 But, in general, if you find yourself policing the idea speech conveys, you鈥檙e engaging in content-based discrimination.
Now let鈥檚 get into what that means for each type of forum on your campus. A quick review: traditional public forums on government property are open to free speech because they historically always have been; designated public forums are open to free speech because the government made it so; and limited public forums are opened by the government to only some categories or speech or speaker.
In a traditional or designated public forum, a content-based regulation on speech must survive what the courts call strict scrutiny. To pass the strict scrutiny test, the government must first show that the restriction is necessary to serve a compelling state interest. As we touched on in the last video, a 鈥渃ompelling鈥 interest is a higher bar for the government to meet than the 鈥渟ignificant鈥 interest required for content-neutral time-place manner restrictions. The Supreme Court, for example, has held that crowd control is a significant interest; and that traffic safety is a compelling interest, while mere aesthetics is not.
In addition to demonstrating a compelling interest, the government must also show that the regulation is narrowly tailored, similarly to the way they must show narrow tailoring for the time, place or manner restrictions we discussed in the last video. The difference here is, just as 鈥渃ompelling鈥 interest is a higher bar for the government than a 鈥渟ignificant鈥 one, the government鈥檚 burden to narrowly tailor is also higher when regulating speech based on content. So, while time, place, and manner restrictions need only not burden 鈥渟ubstantially more speech than necessary,鈥 content-based restrictions must use the 鈥least restrictive means鈥 to further the government鈥檚 compelling interest. Strict scrutiny is a deliberately high hurdle to clear, meaning that most content-based restrictions on speech in traditional or designated public forums will be struck down.
On the other hand, when a public college or university creates a limited public forum 鈥 say, opens the walls of the Natural Science building up for posting flyers related to upcoming events, or invites public comment at a campus 鈥渢own hall鈥 鈥 the school can establish boundaries regarding both who may speak and what they can talk about. This is the one time the government can restrict a forum based on content: in a place that wouldn鈥檛 otherwise be open for speech, the government can open it for a limited purpose. However, once the government has done that, it may only exclude speech that reasonably falls outside the forum鈥檚 purpose, and it may never restrict speech based on viewpoint.
Reasonable restrictions have a specific meaning in this context: they have to clearly define what speech is permitted in the forum, and what isn鈥檛. If a restriction is too vague, different administrators may come to different conclusions. The Supreme Court has held, for example, that merely prohibiting 鈥減olitical鈥 speech from a forum provides no 鈥渟ensible basis for distinguishing what may come in from what must stay out.鈥 What counts as political to one administrator might not count for another. Even in a limited public forum, administrators cannot have unbridled discretion to police speech.
Viewpoint-based restrictions 鈥 restrictions that prohibit not a topic of speech, generally, but just one side of a debate 鈥 are heavily disfavored and are presumptively unconstitutional. Courts rarely, if ever, uphold these restrictions. The foundational Supreme Court opinion for this principle comes from the 1995 case Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of University of Virginia. In Rosenberger, the University of Virginia used public money to subsidize publishing costs for nonreligious student groups, but denied those funds to a Christian student newspaper. The Court held that, although a student activities fund was more a 鈥渕etaphysical鈥 forum than a geographic one, the school was nevertheless prohibited from excluding speakers because of the particular perspective the speakers expressed.
Viewpoint discrimination can occur both in the text of a school鈥檚 regulation, or in the way a school applies what would otherwise appear to be a viewpoint neutral policy. On the face of a regulation, a policy restricting 鈥渙ffensive鈥 or 鈥渋nappropriate鈥 speech, for example, necessarily discriminates based on viewpoint. First, what gives 鈥渙ffense鈥 is in the eye of the beholder 鈥 if you鈥檙e censoring or punishing speech because you do not like it, you鈥檙e discriminating based on viewpoint. Second, the Supreme Court has held that giving offense is, itself, a viewpoint and is protected. Policies with language banning 鈥渙ffensive鈥 speech will be struck down as facial violations of student or faculty free speech rights.
Policies that don鈥檛 appear to discriminate based on viewpoint on their face can also violate the First Amendment if administrators enforce them in viewpoint discriminatory ways. For example, many schools impose security fees when student groups have outside speakers on campus. These policies may appear to be viewpoint, or even content neutral, but schools routinely require higher fees for controversial speakers, effectively levying a tax on speech they believe might offend or be controversial. The Supreme Court has held that security policies that give government officials discretion to set fee amounts violate the First Amendment because 鈥淸t]he fee assessed will depend on the administrator鈥檚 measure of the amount of hostility likely to be created by the speech based on its content. Those wishing to express views unpopular with bottle throwers, for example, may have to pay more for their permit.鈥 If you apply any policy in a way that favors some viewpoints over others, you鈥檙e violating your campus community鈥檚 rights to be free from viewpoint discrimination.
So far in this unit, you鈥檝e learned about the kinds of forums you may find on your campus; you鈥檝e learned about time, place and manner restrictions; and now you鈥檝e learned about content- and viewpoint-based discrimination. In the next lessons, we鈥檒l teach you about state laws that may restrict how you address each of these issues, and then give you some practical tips for how to make sure you鈥檙e following the First Amendment when drafting or enforcing policies on campus.
Suggested Resources:
"Memorandum in Support of Motion for Preliminary Injunction" in Flores v. Bennett (2022)
Zach Greenberg Reed/Reagan CLE PowerPoint (available upon request)
Reed v. Town of Gilbert (2015)
Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of University of Virginia (1995)
Matal v. Tam (2017)
Alex Morey, "UC Berkeley agrees to pay $70k, change policies, in speech suit settlement" (2018)
Heffron v. International Society for Krishna Consciousness (1981)